agree in some of their properties, and to differ in
others; the common effect is to be attributed to the
properties in which they agree, and not to those in
which they differ. 2. Not to account for the
effect of a natural object from the effect of an artificial
object. 3. Not to account for the effect of any
natural object from a conclusion of our reason concerning
its uses, if a natural cause may be assigned. 4.
Not to admit any determinate quantity, or any relation
of quantity, as the cause of a certain effect, if
the effect is produced by different or opposite measures
and relations; or if these measures and relations
may exist, and yet the effect may not be produced.
These are the rules which I have chiefly followed,
whilst I examined into the power of proportion considered
as a natural cause; and these, if he thinks them just,
I request the reader to carry with him throughout the
following discussion; whilst we inquire, in the first
place, in what things we find this quality of beauty;
next, to see whether in these we can find any assignable
proportions in such a manner as ought to convince us
that our idea of beauty results from them. We
shall consider this pleasing power as it appears in
vegetables, in the inferior animals, and in man.
Turning our eyes to the vegetable creation, we find
nothing there so beautiful as flowers; but flowers
are almost of every sort of shape, and of every sort
of disposition; they are turned and fashioned into
an infinite variety of forms; and from these forms
botanists have given them their names, which are almost
as various. What proportion do we discover between
the stalks and the leaves of flowers, or between the
leaves and the pistils? How does the slender stalk
of the rose agree with the bulky head under which
it bends? but the rose is a beautiful flower; and
can we undertake to say that it does not owe a great
deal of its beauty even to that disproportion; the
rose is a large flower, yet it grows upon a small
shrub; the flower of the apple is very small, and
grows upon a large tree; yet the rose and the apple
blossom are both beautiful, and the plants that bear
them are most engagingly attired, notwithstanding
this disproportion. What by general consent is
allowed to be a more beautiful object than an orange-tree,
nourishing at once with its leaves, its blossoms,
and its fruit? but it is in vain that we search here
for any proportion between the height, the breadth,
or anything else concerning the dimensions of the
whole, or concerning the relation of the particular
parts to each other. I grant that we may observe
in many flowers something of a regular figure, and
of a methodical disposition of the leaves. The
rose has such a figure and such a disposition of its
petals; but in an oblique view, when this figure is
in a good measure lost, and the order of the leaves
confounded, it yet retains its beauty; the rose is
even more beautiful before it is full blown; in the
bud; before this exact figure is formed; and this
is not the only instance wherein method and exactness,
the soul of proportion, are found rather prejudicial
than serviceable to the cause of beauty.