is punished. Among the Karens of India, if a
man is found with poison in his possession, he is
bound and placed for three days in the hot sun, his
poison is destroyed, and he is pledged not to obtain
any more. If he is suspected of killing anyone,
he is executed.[204] Particularly distressing modes
of death, and other means of penalizing death by poison
more severely than motor modes of killing, were adopted.
The Chinese punish the preparation of poisons or capture
of poisonous animals with beheading, confiscation,
and banishment of wife and children. In Athens
insanity caused by poison was punished with death.
The
Sachsenspiegel provides death by fire.
In the lawbook of the tsar Wachtang a double composition
price was exacted for death by poison. And in
ancient Wales death and confiscation were the penalty
for death by poison, and death or banishment the penalty
of the manufacturer of poisons. The same quality
of disapproval is expressed in early law of sorcery,
and it is unnecessary to give details of this also.
But, stated in emotional terms, both poison and sorcery,
and other underhand practices arouse one of the most
distressing of the emotions—the emotion
of dread, if we understand by this term that form
of fear which has no tangible or visible embodiment,
which is apprehended but not located, and which in
consequence cannot be resisted; the distress, in fact,
lying in the inability to function. The organism
which has developed structure and function through
action is unsatisfied by an un-motor mode of decision.
We thus detect in the love of fair play, in the Golden
Rule, and in all moral practices a motor element;
and with changing conditions there is progressively
a tendency, mediated by natural selection and conscious
choice, to select those modes of reaction in which
the element of chance is as far as possible eliminated.
This preference for functional over chance or quasi-chance
forms of decision is expressed first within the group,
but is slowly extended, along with increasing commercial
communication, treaties of peace, and with supernatural
assistance, to neighboring groups. The case of
Odysseus is an instance of a moment in the life of
the race when a disapproval is becoming of general
application.
On our assumption that morality is dependent on strains,
and that its development is due to the advantage of
regulating these strains, we may readily understand
why most of the canons of morality are functions of
the katabolic male activity. Theft, arson, rape,
murder, burglary, highway robbery, treason, and the
like, are natural accompaniments of the more aggressive
male disposition; the male is par excellence
both the hero and the criminal. But on the side
of the sex we might expect to find the female disposition
setting the standards of morality, since reproduction
is even a greater part of her nature than of man’s.
On the contrary, however, we find the male standpoint
carried over and applied to the reproductive process,