them. Henry did all he could to put himself in
the wrong. His atrocious request that More “would
not use many words on the scaffold” makes one
hate him after the lapse of well-nigh four hundred
years. The question, however, is not one of personal
feeling. Good men go wrong. Bad men are made
by providence to be instruments for good. It
is not More, nor Fisher, it is the Bluebeard of the
children’s history-books who gave England Miles
Coverdale’s Bible, who freed her from the yoke
that oppressed France till the Revolution, and oppresses
Spain to-day. Froude’s first four volumes
are an eloquent indictment of Ultramontanism, a plea
for the Reformation, a sustained argument for English
liberties and freedom of thought. No such book
can be impartial in the sense of admitting that there
is as much to be said on one side as on the other.
Froude replied to The Edinburgh Review in Fraser’s
Magazine for September, 1858, and in the following
month the reviewer retorted. He did not really
shake the foundation of Froude’s case, which
was the same as Luther’s. Luther, like
Froude, was no democrat. To both of them the
Reformation was a protest against ecclesiastical tyranny,
or for spiritual freedom. “The comedy has
ended in a marriage,” said Erasmus of Luther
and Luther’s wife. It was not a comedy,
and it had not ended.
Froude sometimes goes too far. When he defends
the Boiling Act, under which human beings were actually
boiled alive in Smithfield, he shakes confidence in
his judgment. He sets too much value upon the
verdicts of Henry’s tribunals, forgetting Macaulay’s
emphatic declaration that State trials before 1688
were murder under the forms of law. Although
the subject of his Prize Essay at Oxford was “The
Influence of the Science of Political Economy upon
the Moral and Social Welfare of a Nation,” he
never to the end of his life understood what political
economy was. Misled by Carlyle, he conceived
it to be a sort of “Gospel,” a rival system
to the Christian religion, instead of useful generalisations
from the observed course of trade. He never got
rid of the idea that Governments could fix the rate
of wages and the price of goods. A more serious
fault found by The Edinburgh reviewer, the ablest of
all Froude’s critics, was the implication rather
than the assertion that Henry viii.’s Parliaments
represented the people. The House of Commons
in the sixteenth century was really chosen through
the Sheriffs by the Crown, and the preambles of the
Statutes, upon which Froude relied as evidence of
contemporary opinion, showed the opinion of the Government
rather than the opinion of the people.