allow that the happiness of the wise man would remain
unimpaired even if he were thrust into the bull of
Phalaris[103]. In another place he admits the
purely Stoic doctrine that virtue is one and indivisible[104].
These opinions, however, he will not allow to be distinctively
Stoic, but appeals to Socrates as his authority for
them[105]. Zeno, who is merely an ignoble craftsman
of words, stole them from the Old Academy. This
is Cicero’s general feeling with regard to Zeno,
and there can be no doubt that he caught it from Antiochus
who, in stealing the doctrines of Zeno, ever stoutly
maintained that Zeno had stolen them before. Cicero,
however, regarded chiefly the ethics of Zeno with
this feeling, while Antiochus so regarded chiefly
the dialectic. It is just in this that the difference
between Antiochus and Cicero lies. To the former
Zeno’s dialectic was true and Socratic, while
the latter treated it as un-Socratic, looking upon
Socrates as the apostle of doubt[106]. On the
whole Cicero was more in accord with Stoic ethics
than Antiochus. Not in all points, however:
for while Antiochus accepted without reserve the Stoic
paradoxes, Cicero hesitatingly followed them, although
he conceded that they were Socratic[107]. Again,
Antiochus subscribed to the Stoic theory that all
emotion was sinful; Cicero, who was very human in his
joys and sorrows, refused it with horror[108].
It must be admitted that on some points Cicero was
inconsistent. In the
De Finibus he argued
that the difference between the Peripatetic and Stoic
ethics was merely one of terms; in the
Tusculan
Disputations he held it to be real. The most
Stoic in tone of all his works are the
Tusculan
Disputations and the
De Officiis.
With regard to physics, I may remark at the outset
that a comparatively small importance was in Cicero’s
time attached to this branch of philosophy. Its
chief importance lay in the fact that ancient theology
was, as all natural theology must be, an appendage
of physical science. The religious element in
Cicero’s nature inclined him very strongly to
sympathize with the Stoic views about the grand universal
operation of divine power. Piety, sanctity, and
moral good, were impossible in any form, he thought,
if the divine government of the universe were denied[109].
It went to Cicero’s heart that Carneades should
have found it necessary to oppose the beautiful Stoic
theology, and he defends the great sceptic by the
plea that his one aim was to arouse men to the investigation
of the truth[110]. At the same time, while really
following the Stoics in physics, Cicero often believed
himself to be following Aristotle. This partly
arose from the actual adoption by the late Peripatetics
of many Stoic doctrines, which they gave out as Aristotelian.
The discrepancy between the spurious and the genuine
Aristotelian views passed undetected, owing to the
strange oblivion into which the most important works
of Aristotle had fallen[111]. Still, Cicero contrives
to correct many of the extravagances of the Stoic
physics by a study of Aristotle and Plato. For
a thorough understanding of his notions about physics,
the Timaeus of Plato, which he knew well and
translated, is especially important. It must not
be forgotten, also, that the Stoic physics were in
the main Aristotelian, and that Cicero was well aware
of the fact.