of his narrow desire for material advancement.
And that, indeed, is the starting-point of modern
effort. Our liberty means the consistent expression
of our personality in media where we find people like-minded
with ourselves in their conception of social life.
The very scale of civilization implies collective plans
and common effort. The constant revision of our
basic notions was inevitable immediately science was
applied to industry. There was thus no reason
to believe that the system of individual interests
for which Smith stood sponsor was more likely to fit
requirements of a new time than one which implied
the national regulation of business enterprise.
The danger in every period of history is lest we take
our own age as the term in institutional evolution.
Private enterprise has the sanction of prescription;
but since the Industrial Revolution the chief lesson
we have had to learn is the unsatisfactory character
of that title. History is an unenviable record
of bad metaphysics used to defend obsolete systems.
It took almost a century after the publication of the
Wealth of Nations for men to realize that its
axioms represented the experience of a definite time.
Smith thought of freedom in the terms most suitable
to his generation and stated them with a largeness
of view which remains impressive even at a century’s
distance.
But nothing is more certain in the history of political
philosophy than that the problem of freedom changes
with each age. The nineteenth century sought
release from political privilege; and it built its
success upon the system prepared by its predecessor.
It can never be too greatly emphasized that in each
age the substance of liberty will be found in what
the dominating forces of that age most greatly want.
With Locke, with Smith, with Hegel and with Marx,
the ultimate hypothesis is always the summary of some
special experience universalized. That does not
mean that the past is worthless. Politics, as
Seeley said, are vulgar unless they are liberalized
by history; and a state which failed to see itself
as a mosaic of ancestral institutions would build its
novelties upon foundations of sand. Suspicions
of collective effort in the eighteenth century ought
not to mean suspicion in the twentieth; to think in
such fashion is to fall into the error for which Lassalle
so finely criticized Hegel. It is as though one
were to confound the accidental phases of the history
of property with the philosophic basis of property
itself. From such an error it is the task of history
above all to free us. For it records the ideals
and doubts of earlier ages as a perennial challenge
to the coming time.