more fitted for the uses of the world, more sensitive
to what is noble in nature—by its contemplation.
At the best Correggio does but please us in our lighter
moments, and we are apt to feel that the pleasure
he has given is of an enervating kind. To expect
obvious morality of any artist is confessedly absurd.
It is not the artist’s province to preach, or
even to teach, except by remote suggestion. Yet
the mind of the artist may be highly moralised, and
then he takes rank not merely with the ministers to
refined pleasure, but also with the educators of the
world. He may, for example, be penetrated with
a just sense of humanity like Shakspere, or with a
sublime temperance like Sophocles, instinct with prophetic
intuition like Michelangelo, or with passionate experience
like Beethoven. The mere sight of the work of
Pheidias is like breathing pure health-giving air.
Milton and Dante were steeped in religious patriotism;
Goethe was pervaded with philosophy, and Balzac with
scientific curiosity. Ariosto, Cervantes, and
even Boccaccio are masters in the mysteries of common
life. In all these cases the tone of the artist’s
mind is felt throughout his work: what he paints,
or sings, or writes, conveys a lesson while it pleases.
On the other hand, depravity in an artist or a poet
percolates through work which has in it nothing positive
of evil, and a very miasma of poisonous influence
may rise from the apparently innocuous creations of
a tainted soul. Now Correggio is moralised in
neither way—neither as a good nor as a bad
man, neither as an acute thinker nor as a deliberate
voluptuary. He is simply sensuous. On his
own ground he is even very fresh and healthy:
his delineation of youthful maternity, for example,
is as true as it is beautiful; and his sympathy with
the gleefulness of children is devoid of affectation.
We have then only to ask ourselves whether the defect
in him of all thought and feeling which is not at
once capable of graceful fleshly incarnation, be sufficient
to lower him in the scale of artists. This question
must of course be answered according to our definition
of the purposes of art. There is no doubt that
the most highly organised art—that which
absorbs the most numerous human qualities and effects
a harmony between the most complex elements—is
the noblest. Therefore the artist who combines
moral elevation and power of thought with a due appreciation
of sensual beauty, is more elevated and more beneficial
than one whose domain is simply that of carnal loveliness.
Correggio, if this be so, must take a comparatively
low rank. Just as we welcome the beautiful athlete
for the radiant life that is in him, but bow before
the personality of Sophocles, whose perfect form enshrined
a noble and highly educated soul, so we gratefully
accept Correggio for his grace, while we approach the
consummate art of Michelangelo with reverent awe.
It is necessary in aesthetics as elsewhere to recognise
a hierarchy of excellence, the grades of which are