spiritual things in each other. But these statements
do not make it clear how Eckhart accounts for the
imperfections of the phenomenal world, which he is
precluded from explaining, as the Neoplatonists did,
by a theory of emanation. Nor can we solve the
difficulty by importing modern theories of evolution
into his system. The idea of the world-history
as a gradual realisation of the Divine Personality
was foreign to Eckhart’s thought. Stoeckl,
indeed, tries to father upon him the doctrine that
the human mind is a necessary organ of the self-development
of God. But this theory cannot be found in Eckhart.
The “necessity” which impels God to “beget
His Son” is not a physical but a moral necessity.
“The good must needs impart itself,” he
says.[242] The fact is that his view of the world
is much nearer to acosmism than to pantheism.
“Nothing hinders us so much from the knowledge
of God as time and place,” he says. He
sees in phenomena only the negation of being, and
it is not clear how he can also regard them as the
abode of the immanent God.[243] It would probably
be true to say that, like most mediaeval thinkers,
he did not feel himself obliged to give a permanent
value to the transitory, and that the world, except
as the temporary abode of immortal spirits, interested
him but little. His neglect of history, including
the earthly life of Christ, is not at all the result
of scepticism about the miraculous. It is simply
due to the feeling that the Divine process in the
“everlasting Now” is a fact of immeasurably
greater importance than any occurrence in the external
world can be.
When a religious writer is suspected of pantheism,
we naturally turn to his treatment of the problem
of evil. To the true pantheist all is equally
divine, and everything for the best or for the worst,
it does not much matter which.[244] Eckhart certainly
does not mean to countenance this absurd theory, but
there are passages in his writings which logically
imply it; and we look in vain for any elucidation,
in his doctrine of sin, of the dark places in his
doctrine of God.[245] In fact, he adds very little
to the Neoplatonic doctrine of the nature of evil.
Like Dionysius, he identifies Being with Good, and
evil, as such, with not-being. Moral evil is
self-will: it is the attempt, on the part of
the creature, to be a particular This or That outside
of God.
But what is most distinctive in Eckhart’s ethics
is the new importance which is given to the doctrine
of immanence. The human soul is a microcosm,
which in a manner contains all things in itself.
At the “apex of the mind” there is a Divine
“spark,” which is so closely akin to God
that it is one with Him, and not merely united to Him.[246]
In his teaching about this “ground of the soul”
Eckhart wavers. His earlier view is that it is
created, and only the medium by which God transforms
us to Himself. But his later doctrine is that
it is uncreated, the immanence of the Being and Nature
of God Himself. “Diess Fuenkelein, das