he is also the greatest of our countrymen in full
possession of a national Italian consciousness.
To liberate Italy, which was in his day “enslaved,
torn and pillaged,” and to make her more powerful,
he would use any means, for to his mind the holiness
of the end justified them completely. In this
he was sharply rebuked by foreigners who were not as
hostile to his means as they were fearful of the end
which he propounded. He advocated therefore the
constitution of a strong Italian state, supported
by the sacrifices and by the blood of the citizens,
not defended by mercenary troops; well-ordered internally,
aggressive and bent on expansion. “Weak
republics,” he said, “have no determination
and can never reach a decision.” (Disc.
I. c. 38). “Weak states were ever dubious
in choosing their course, and slow deliberations are
always harmful.” (Disc. I. c. 10).
And again: “Whoso undertakes to govern
a multitude either in a regime of liberty or in a monarchy,
without previously making sure of those who are hostile
to the new order of things builds a short-lived state.”
(Disc. I. c. 16). And further on “the
dictatorial authority helped and did not harm the
Roman republic” (Disc. I. c. 34), and “Kings
and republics lacking in national troops both for
offense and defense should be ashamed of their existence.”
(Disc. I. c. 21). And again: “Money
not only does not protect you but rather it exposes
you to plundering assaults. Nor can there be
a more false opinion than that which says that money
is the sinews of war. Not money but good soldiers
win battles.” (Disc. I. II. c. 10).
“The country must be defended with ignominy or
with glory and in either way it is nobly defended.”
(Disc. III. c. 41). “And with dash
and boldness people often capture what they never would
have obtained by ordinary means.” (Disc.
III. c. 44). Machiavelli was not only a great
political authority, he taught the mastery of energy
and will. Fascism learns from him not only its
doctrines but its action as well.
Different from Machiavelli’s, in mental attitude,
in cultural preparation, and in manner of presentation,
G.B. Vico must yet be connected with the great
Florentine from whom in a certain way he seems to
proceed. In the heyday of “natural law”
Vico is decidedly opposed to ius naturale and
in his attacks against its advocates, Grotius, Seldenus
and Pufendorf, he systematically assails the abstract,
rationalistic, and utilitarian principles of the XVIII
century. As Montemayor justly says:[4] “While
the ‘natural jurists’, basing justice
and state on utility and interest and grounding human
certitude on reason, were striving to draft permanent
codes and construct the perfect state, Vico strongly
asserted the social nature of man, the ethical character
of the juridical consciousness and its growth through
the history of humanity rather than in sacred history.
Vico therefore maintains that doctrines must begin
with those subjects which take up and explain the