to the propagation of ideas which they had acquired
together from Jean Jacques, and from the Greeks to
whom Jean Jacques had sent them for example and instruction.[199]
No doubt the condition of France after 1792 must naturally
have struck any one too deeply imbued with the spirit
of the Social Contract to look beneath the surface
of the society with which the Convention had to deal,
as urgently inviting a lawgiver of the ancient stamp.
The old order in church and state had been swept away,
no organs for the performance of the functions of
national life were visible, the moral ideas which
had bound the social elements together in the extinct
monarchy seemed to be permanently sapped. A politician
who had for years been dreaming about Minos and Lycurgus
and Calvin, especially if he lived in a state with
such a tradition of centralisation as ruled in France,
was sure to suppose that here was the scene and the
moment for a splendid repetition on an immense scale
of those immortal achievements. The futility
of the attempt was the practical and ever memorable
illustration of the defect of Rousseau’s geometrical
method. It was one thing to make laws for the
handful of people who lived in Geneva in the sixteenth
century, united in religious faith, and accepting
the same form and conception of the common good.
It was a very different thing to try to play Calvin
over some twenty-five millions of a heterogeneously
composed nation, abounding in variations of temperament,
faith, laws, and habits and weltering in unfathomable
distractions. The French did indeed at length
invite a heaven-sent stranger from Corsica to make
laws for them, but not until he had set his foot upon
their neck; and even Napoleon Bonaparte, who had begun
life like the rest of his generation by writing Rousseauite
essays, made a swift return to the historic method
in the equivocal shape of the Concordat.
Not only were Rousseau’s schemes of polity conceived
from the point of view of a small territory with a
limited population. “You must not,”
he says in one place, “make the abuses of great
states an objection to a writer who would fain have
none but small ones."[200] Again, when he said that
in a truly free state the citizens performed all their
services to the community with their arms and none
by money, and that he looked upon the corvee (or compulsory
labour on the public roads) as less hostile to freedom
than taxes,[201] he showed that he was thinking of
a state not greatly passing the dimensions of a parish.
This was not the only defect of his schemes. They
assumed a sort of state of nature in the minds of
the people with whom the lawgiver had to deal.
Saint Just made the same assumption afterwards, and
trusted to his military school to erect on these bare
plots whatever superstructure he might think fit to
appoint. A society that had for so many centuries
been organised and moulded by a powerful and energetic
church, armed with a definite doctrine, fixing the
same moral tendencies in a long series of successive