only to comment is no more than a development of the
chorus. Here is the problem to which Nietzsche
endeavours to find an answer. He finds it, unlike
the learned persons who study Greek texts, among the
roots of things, in the very making of the universe.
Art arises, he tells us, from the conflict of the
two creative spirits, symbolised by the Greeks in the
two gods, Apollo and Dionysus; and he names the one
the Apollonian spirit, which we see in plastic art,
and the other the Dionysiac spirit, which we see in
music. Apollo is the god of dreams, Dionysus the
god of intoxication; the one represents for us the
world of appearances, the other is, as it were, the
voice of things in themselves. The chorus, then,
which arose out of the hymns to Dionysus, is the “lyric
cry,” the vital ecstasy; the drama is the projection
into vision, into a picture, of the exterior, temporary
world of forms. “We now see that the stage
and the action are conceived only as vision:
that the sole ‘reality’ is precisely the
chorus, which itself produces the vision, and expresses
it by the aid of the whole symbolism of dance, sound,
and word.” In the admirable phrase of Schiller,
the chorus is “a living rampart against reality,”
against that false reality of daily life which is
a mere drapery of civilisation, and has nothing to
do with the primitive reality of nature. The
realistic drama begins with Euripides; and Euripides,
the casuist, the friend of Socrates (whom Nietzsche
qualifies as the true decadent, an “instrument
of decomposition,” the slayer of art, the father
of modern science), brings tragedy to an end, as he
substitutes pathos for action, thought for contemplation,
and passionate sentiments for the primitive ecstasy.
“Armed with the scourge of its syllogisms, an
optimist dialectic drives the music out of tragedy:
that is to say, destroys the very essence of tragedy,
an essence which can be interpreted only as a manifestation
and objectivation of Dionysiac states, as a visible
symbol of music, as the dream-world of a Dionysiac
intoxication.” There are many pages, scattered
throughout his work, in which Pater has dealt with
some of the Greek problems very much in the spirit
of Nietzsche; with that problem, for instance, of the
“blitheness and serenity” of the Greek
spirit, and of the gulf of horror over which it seems
to rest, suspended as on the wings of the condor.
That myth of Dionysus Zagreus, “a Bacchus who
had been in hell,” which is the foundation of
the marvellous new myth of “Denys l’Auxerrois,”
seems always to be in the mind of Nietzsche, though
indeed he refers to it but once, and passingly.
Pater has shown, as Nietzsche shows in greater detail
and with a more rigorous logic, that this “serenity”
was but an accepted illusion, and all Olympus itself
but “intermediary,” an escape, through
the aesthetics of religion, from the trouble at the
heart of things; art, with its tragic illusions of
life, being another form of escape. To Nietzsche
the world and existence justify themselves only as