the test of perfect love. It is the sign
of it, for, when love can show itself natural
and true, one may conclude that it is purified
of its unavowable imperfections or defects, of its
alloy of wretched and petty passions, its grossness,
its chimerical notions, that it has become strong
and healthy and vigorous. It is the ordeal
of it, for to show itself natural, to be always true,
without shrinking, it must have all the lovable qualities,
and have them without seeking, as a second nature.
What we call ‘natural,’ is indeed
really acquired; it is the gift of a physical
and moral evolution which it is precisely the object
of modesty to keep. Modesty is the feeling
of the true, that is to say, of the healthy, in
love; it long exists as a vision, not yet attained;
vague, yet sufficiently clear for all that deviates
from it to be repelled as offensive and painful.
At first, a remote and seemingly inaccessible
ideal, as it comes nearer it grows human and individual,
and emerges from the region of dream, ceasing
not to be loved as ideal, even when it is possessed
as real.
“At first sight, it seems paradoxical to define modesty as an aspiration towards truth in love; it seems, on the contrary, to be an altogether factitious feeling. But to simplify the problem, we have to suppose modesty reduced to its normal functions, disengaged from its superstitions, its variegated customs and prejudices, the true modesty of simple and healthy natures, as far removed from prudery as from immodesty. And what we term the natural, or the true in love, is the singular mingling of two forms of imaginations, wrongly supposed to be incompatible: ideal aspiration and the sense for the realities of life. Thus defined, modesty not only repudiates that cold and dissolving criticism which deprives love of all poetry, and prepares the way for a brutal realism; it also excludes that light and detached imagination which floats above love, the mere idealism of heroic sentiments, which cherishes poetic illusions, and passes, without seeing it, the love that is real and alive. True modesty implies a love not addressed to the heroes of vain romances, but to living people, with their feet on the earth. But on the other hand, modesty is the respect of love; if it is not shocked by its physical necessities, if it accepts physiological and psychological conditions, it also maintains the ideal of those moral proprieties outside of which, for all of us, love cannot be enjoyed. When love is really felt, and not vainly imagined, modesty is the requirement of an ideal of dignity, conceived as the very condition of that love. Separate modesty from love, that is, from love which is not floating in the air, but crystallized around a real person, and its psychological reality, its poignant and tragic character, disappears.” (Dugas, “La Pudeur,” Revue Philosophique, Nov., 1903.) So conceived, modesty becomes a virtue, almost identical with the Roman modestia.