my children!” as the curtain fell. Moliere
evidently took the attitude that since any ending
whatsoever must be in the nature of an artifice, and
contrary to the laws of life, he might as well falsify
upon the pleasant side and send his auditors happy
to their homes. Shakespeare took the same attitude
in many comedies, of which As You Like It may
be chosen as an illustration. The sudden reform
of Oliver and the tardy repentance of the usurping
duke are both untrue to life and illogical as art;
but Shakespeare decided to throw probability and logic
to the winds in order to close his comedy with a general
feeling of good-will. But this easy answer to
the question cannot be accepted in the case of the
serious drama; for—and this is a point
that is very often missed—in proportion
as the dramatic struggle becomes more vital and momentous,
the audience demands more and more that it shall be
fought out fairly, and that even the characters it
favors shall receive no undeserved assistance from
the dramatist. This instinct of the crowd—the
instinct by which its demand for fairness is proportioned
to the importance of the struggle—may be
studied by any follower of professional base-ball.
The spectators at a ball-game are violently partisan
and always want the home team to win. In any unimportant
game—if the opposing teams, for instance,
have no chance to win the pennant—the crowd
is glad of any questionable decision by the umpires
that favors the home team. But in any game in
which the pennant is at stake, a false or bad decision,
even though it be rendered in favor of the home team,
will be received with hoots of disapproval. The
crowd feels, in such a case, that it cannot fully
enjoy the sense of victory unless the victory be fairly
won. For the same reason, when any important play
which sets out to end unhappily is given a sudden
twist which brings about an arbitrary happy ending,
the audience is likely to be displeased. And there
is yet another reason for this displeasure. An
audience may enjoy both farce and comedy without believing
them; but it cannot fully enjoy a serious play unless
it believes the story. In the serious drama, an
ending, to be enjoyable, must be credible; in other
words, it must, for the sake of human interest, satisfy
the strict logic of art. We arrive, therefore,
at the paradox that although, in the final act, the
comic dramatist may achieve popularity by renouncing
the laws of art, the serious dramatist can achieve
popularity only by adhering rigidly to a pattern of
artistic truth.
This is a point that is rarely understood by people who look at the general question from the point of view of the box-office; they seldom appreciate the fact that a serious play which logically demands an unhappy ending will make more money if it is planned in accordance with the sternest laws of art than if it is given an arbitrary happy ending in which the audience cannot easily believe. The public wants to be pleased, but it wants even more to be satisfied.