issue with sin in the world, that there is no way
of attaining goodness except through conflict with
evil, and that moral life, as the poet so frequently
insists, is a process which converts all actual attainment
into a dead self, from which we can rise to higher
things—a self, therefore, which is relatively
evil—would, and does, inspire morality.
It is the deification of evil not negated or overcome,
of evil as it is in itself and apart from all process,
which destroys morality. And the same is equally
true of a pantheistic optimism, which asserts that
all things
are good. But it is not true
of a Christian optimism, which asserts that all things
are
working together for good. For such
optimism implies that the process of negating or overcoming
evil is essential to the attainment of goodness; it
does not imply that evil, as evil, is ever good.
Evil is unreal, only in the sense that it cannot withstand
the power which is set against it. It is not
mere
semblance, a mere negation or absence of being; it
is opposed to the good, and its opposition can be
overcome, only by the moral effort which it calls
forth. An optimistic faith of this kind can find
room for morality; and, indeed, it furnishes it with
the religious basis it needs. Browning, however,
has confused these two forms of optimism; and, therefore,
he has been driven to condemn knowledge, because he
knew no alternative but that of either making evil
eternally real, or making it absolutely unreal.
A third alternative, however, is supplied by the conception
of moral evolution. Knowledge of the conditions
on which good can be attained—a knowledge
that amounts to conviction—is the spring
of all moral effort; whereas an attitude of permanent
doubt as to the distinction between good and evil
would paralyse it. Such a doubt must be solved
before man can act at all, or choose one end rather
than another. All action implies belief, and
the ardour and vigour of moral action can only come
from a belief which is whole-hearted.
The further assertion, which the poet makes in La
Saisiaz, and repeats elsewhere, that sure knowledge
of the consequences that follow good and evil actions
would necessarily lead to the choice of good and the
avoidance of evil, and destroy morality by destroying
liberty of choice, raises the whole question of the
relation of knowledge and conduct, and cannot be adequately
discussed here. It may be said, however, that
it rests upon a confusion between two forms of necessity:
namely, natural and spiritual necessity. In asserting
that knowledge of the consequences of evil would determine
human action in a necessary way, the poet virtually
treats man as if he were a natural being. But
the assumption that man is responsible and liable
to punishment, involves that he is capable of withstanding
all such determination. And knowledge does not
and cannot lead to such necessary determination.
Reason brings freedom; for reason constitutes the
ends of action.