sale of fungibles, and therefore the just price in
such a contract was the return of fungibles of the
same value as those lent. If the particular fungible
sold happened to be money, the estimation of the just
price was a simple matter—it was the return
of an amount of money of equal value. As money
happened to be the universal measure of value, this
simply meant the return of the same amount of money.
Those who maintained that something additional might
be claimed for the use of the money lost sight of
the fact that the money was incapable of being used
apart from its being consumed.[1] To ask for payment
for the sale of a thing which not only did not exist,
but which was quite incapable of existence, was clearly
to ask for something for nothing—which
obviously offended against the first principles of
commutative justice. ‘He that is not bound
to lend,’ says Aquinas in another part of the
same article, ’may accept repayment for what
he has done, but he must not exact more. Now
he is repaid according to equality of justice if he
is repaid as much as he lent, wherefore, if he exacts
more for the usufruct of a thing which has no other
use but the consumption of its substance, he exacts
a price of something non-existent, and so his exaction
is unjust.’[2] And in the next article the principle
that
mutuum is a sale appears equally clearly:
’Money cannot be sold for a greater sum than
the amount lent, which has to be paid back.’[3]
[Footnote 1: Aquinas did not lose sight of the
fact that money might, in certain cases, be used apart
from being consumed—for instance, when
it was not used as a means of exchange, but as an ornament.
He gives the example of money being sewn up and sealed
in a bag to prevent its being spent, and in this condition
lent for any purpose. In this case, of course,
the transaction would not be a mutuum, but
a locatio et conductio, and therefore a price
could be charged for the use of the money (Quaestiones
Disputatae de Malo, Q. xiii. art. iv. ad. 15,
quoted in Cronin’s Ethics, vol. ii. p.
332).]
[Footnote 2: II. ii. 78, 1, ad. 5.]
[Footnote 3: II. ii. 78, 2, ad. 4. Biel
distinguishes three kinds of exchange: of goods
for goods, or barter; of goods for money, or sale;
and of money for money; and adds, ’In his contractibus
... generaliter justitia in hoc consistit quod fiant
sine fraude, et servetur aequalitas substantiae, qualitatis,
quantitatis in commutatis (Op. cit., IV. xv.
1). Buridan says that usury is contrary to natural
law ’ex conditione justitiae quae in aequalitate
damni et lucri consistit; quoniam injustum est pro
re semel commutata pluries pretium recipere’
(In Lib. Pol., iv. 6).]