intellect of our time the wild investigators of the
school of Paracelsus seem to be the very crown and
flower of futility, they are collectors of straws and
careful misers of dust. But for all that Browning
was right. Any critic who understands the true
spirit of mediaeval science can see that he was right;
no critic can see how right he was unless he understands
the spirit of mediaeval science as thoroughly as he
did. In the character of Paracelsus, Browning
wished to paint the dangers and disappointments which
attend the man who believes merely in the intellect.
He wished to depict the fall of the logician; and with
a perfect and unerring instinct he selected a man
who wrote and spoke in the tradition of the Middle
Ages, the most thoroughly and even painfully logical
period that the world has ever seen. If he had
chosen an ancient Greek philosopher, it would have
been open to the critic to have said that that philosopher
relied to some extent upon the most sunny and graceful
social life that ever flourished. If he had made
him a modern sociological professor, it would have
been possible to object that his energies were not
wholly concerned with truth, but partly with the solid
and material satisfaction of society. But the
man truly devoted to the things of the mind was the
mediaeval magician. It is a remarkable fact that
one civilisation does not satisfy itself by calling
another civilisation wicked—it calls it
uncivilised. We call the Chinese barbarians, and
they call us barbarians. The mediaeval state,
like China, was a foreign civilisation, and this was
its supreme characteristic, that it cared for the
things of the mind for their own sake. To complain
of the researches of its sages on the ground that
they were not materially fruitful, is to act as we
should act in telling a gardener that his roses were
not as digestible as our cabbages. It is not only
true that the mediaeval philosophers never discovered
the steam-engine; it is quite equally true that they
never tried. The Eden of the Middle Ages was
really a garden, where each of God’s flowers—truth
and beauty and reason—flourished for its
own sake, and with its own name. The Eden of
modern progress is a kitchen garden.
It would have been hard, therefore, for Browning to
have chosen a better example for his study of intellectual
egotism than Paracelsus. Modern life accuses
the mediaeval tradition of crushing the intellect;
Browning, with a truer instinct, accuses that tradition
of over-glorifying it. There is, however, another
and even more important deduction to be made from
the moral of Paracelsus. The usual accusation
against Browning is that he was consumed with logic;
that he thought all subjects to be the proper pabulum
of intellectual disquisition; that he gloried chiefly
in his own power of plucking knots to pieces and rending
fallacies in two; and that to this method he sacrificed
deliberately, and with complete self-complacency, the
element of poetry and sentiment. To people who
imagine Browning to have been this frigid believer
in the intellect there is only one answer necessary
or sufficient. It is the fact that he wrote a
play designed to destroy the whole of this intellectualist
fallacy at the age of twenty-three.