treatise can doubt for a moment, that its author believed
in the future punishment of the wicked,—and
in the future
endless punishment of the incorrigibly
wicked, because there is not the slightest hint or
expectation of any exercise of mercy on the part of
this Divinity whose vengeance, though slow, is sure
and inevitable.[3] Some theorists tell us that the
doctrine of endless punishment contradicts the instincts
of the natural reason, and that it has no foundation
in the constitution of the human soul. We invite
them to read and ponder well, the speculations of
one of the most thoughtful of pagans upon this subject,
and tell us if they see any streaks or rays of light
in it; if they see any inkling, any jot or tittle,
of the doctrine of the Divine pity there. We
challenge them to discover in this tract of Plutarch
the slightest token, or sign, of the Divine mercy.
The author believes in a hell for the wicked, and
an elysium for the good; but those who go to hell
go there upon principles of
justice, and those
who go to elysium go there upon the
same principles.
It is justice that must place men in Tartarus, and
it is justice that must place them in Elysium.
In paganism, men must earn their heaven. The idea
of
mercy,—of clemency towards a
transgressor, of pity towards a criminal,—is
entirely foreign to the thoughts of Plutarch, so far
as they can be gathered from this tract. It is
the clear and terrible doctrine of the pagan sage,
that unless a man can make good his claim to eternal
happiness upon the ground of law and justice,—unless
he merits it by good works,—there is no
hope for him in the other world.
The idea of a forgiving and tender mercy in the Supreme
Being, exercised towards a creature whom justice would
send to eternal retribution, nowhere appears in the
best pagan ethics. And why should it? What
evidence or proof has the human mind, apart from the
revelations made to it in the Old and New Testaments,
that God will ever forgive sin, or ever show mercy?
In thinking upon the subject, our reason perceives,
intuitively, that God must of necessity punish transgression;
and it perceives with equal intuitiveness that there
is no corresponding necessity that He should pardon
it. We say with confidence and positiveness:
“God must be just;” but we cannot say with
any certainty or confidence at all: “God
must be merciful.” The Divine mercy is an
attribute which is perfectly free and optional, in
its exercises, and therefore we cannot tell beforehand
whether it will or will not be shown to transgressors.
We know nothing at all about it, until we hear some
word from the lips of God Himself upon the point.
When He opens the heavens, and speaks in a clear tone
to the human race, saying, “I will forgive your
iniquities,” then, and not till then, do they
know the fact. In reference to all those procedures
which, like the punishment of transgression, are fixed
and necessary, because they are founded in the eternal