in other individuals, for inherence (
samavaya)
according to Prabhakara is not an eternal entity but
an entity which is both produced and not produced
according as the thing in which it exists is non-eternal
or eternal, and it is not regarded as one as Nyaya
holds, but as many, according as there is the infinite
number of things in which it exists. When any
individual is destroyed, the class-character does
not go elsewhere, nor subsist in that individual,
nor is itself destroyed, but it is only the inherence
of class-character with that individual that ceases
to exist. With the destruction of an individual
or its production it is a new relation of inherence
that is destroyed or produced. But the class-character
or jati has no separate existence apart from the individuals
as Nyaya supposes. Apprehension of jati is essentially
the apprehension of the class-character of a thing
in relation to other similar things of that class
by the perception of the common characteristics.
But Prabhakara would not admit the existence of a
highest genus satta (being) as acknowledged by Nyaya.
He argues that the existence of class-character is
apprehended because we find that the individuals of
a class possess some common characteristic possessed
by all the heterogeneous and disparate things of the
world as can give rise to the conception of a separate
jati as satta, as demanded by the naiyayikas.
That all things are said to be
sat (existing)
is more or less a word or a name without the corresponding
apprehension of a common quality. Our experience
always gives us concrete existing individuals, but
we can never experience such a highest genus as pure
existence or being, as it has no concrete form which
may be perceived. When we speak of a thing as
sat, we do not mean that it is possessed of
any such class-characters as satta (being); what we
mean is simply that the individual has its specific
existence or svarupasatta.
382
Thus the Nyaya view of perception as taking only the
thing in its pure being apart from qualities, etc,
(sanmatra-vi@sayam pratyak@sa@m) is made untenable
by Prabhakara, as according to him the thing is perceived
direct with all its qualities. According to Kumarila
however jati is not something different from the individuals
comprehended by it and it is directly perceived.
Kumarila’s view of jati is thus similar to that
held by Sa@mkhya, namely that when we look at an individual
from one point of view (jati as identical with the
individual), it is the individual that lays its stress
upon our consciousness and the notion of jati becomes
latent, but when we look at it from another point of
view (the individual as identical with jati) it is
the jati which presents itself to consciousness, and
the aspect as individual becomes latent. The
apprehension as jati or as individual is thus only
a matter of different points of view or angles of
vision from which we look at a thing. Quite in
harmony with the conception of jati, Kumarila holds
that the relation of inherence is not anything which
is distinct from the things themselves in which it
is supposed to exist, but only a particular aspect
or phase of the things themselves (S’lokavarttika,
Pratyak@sasutra, 149, 150, abhedat samavayo’stu
svarupam dharmadharmi@no@h), Kumarila agrees with
Prabhakara that jati is perceived by the senses (tatraikabuddhinirgrahya
jatirindriyagocara).