A History of Indian Philosophy, Volume 1 eBook

This eBook from the Gutenberg Project consists of approximately 756 pages of information about A History of Indian Philosophy, Volume 1.

A History of Indian Philosophy, Volume 1 eBook

This eBook from the Gutenberg Project consists of approximately 756 pages of information about A History of Indian Philosophy, Volume 1.
An inference could be for one’s own self (svarthanumana) or for the sake of convincing others (pararthanumana).  In the latter case, when it was necessary that an inference should be put explicitly in an unambiguous manner, live propositions (avayavas) were regarded as necessary, namely pratijna (e.g. the hill is fiery), hetu (since it has smoke), udahara@na (where there is smoke there is fire, as in the kitchen), upanaya (this hill has smoke), niga@mana (therefore it has got

_______________________________________________________
_____________

[Footnote 1:  Vatsyaya@na’s bhasya, Udyotakara’s Varttika and Tatparyya@tika, I.i. 5.]

354

fire).  Kevalanvayi is that type of inference, the vyapti of which could not be based on any negative instance, as in the case “this object has a name, since it is an object of knowledge (ida@m, vacyam prameyatvat).”  Now no such case is known which is not an object of knowledge; we cannot therefore know of any case where there was no object of knowledge (prameyatva) and no name (vacyatva); the vyapti here has therefore to be based necessarily on cases of agreement—­wherever there is prameyatva or an object of knowledge, there is vacyatva or name.  The third form of kevalavyatireki is that where positive instances in agreement cannot be found, such as in the case of the inference that earth differs from other elements in possessing the specific quality of smell, since all that does not differ from other elements is not earth, such as water; here it is evident that there cannot be any positive instance of agreement and the concomitance has to be taken from negative instances.  There is only one instance, which is exactly the proposition of our inference—­earth differs from other elements, since it has the special qualities of earth.  This inference could be of use only in those cases where we had to infer anything by reason of such special traits of it as was possessed by it and it alone.

Upamana and S’abda.

The third prama@na, which is admitted by Nyaya and not by Vais’e@sika, is upamana, and consists in associating a thing unknown before with its name by virtue of its similarity with some other known thing.  Thus a man of the city who has never seen a wild ox (gavaya) goes to the forest, asks a forester—­“what is gavaya?” and the forester replies—­“oh, you do not know it, it is just like a cow”; after hearing this from the forester he travels on, and on seeing a gavaya and finding it to be similar to a cow he forms the opinion that this is a gavaya.  This knowing an hitherto unknown thing by virtue of its similarity to a known thing is called upamana.  If some forester had pointed out a gavaya to a man of the city and had told him that it was called a gavaya, then also the man would have known the animal by the name gavaya, but then this would have been due to testimony (s’abda-prama@na).  The knowledge is said to be generated by the upamana process when the association of the unknown animal with its name is made by the observer

Copyrights
Project Gutenberg
A History of Indian Philosophy, Volume 1 from Project Gutenberg. Public domain.