men could not raise within us such affections, or
make us careful about anything beyond external deportment.
Nor could rewards from God, or the wish for self-approbation,
create such affections, although, on the supposition
of their existence, these may well help to foster them.
It is benevolent
dispositions that we morally
approve; but dispositions are not to be raised by
will. Moreover, they are often found where there
has been least thought of cultivating them; and, sometimes,
in the form of parental affection, gratitude, &c.,
they are followed so little for the sake of honour
and reward, that though their absence is condemned,
they are themselves hardly accounted virtuous at all.
He then rebuts the idea that generous affections are
selfish, because by
sympathy we make the pleasures
and pains of others our own. Sympathy is a real
fact, but has regard only to the distress or suffering
beheld or imagined in others, whereas generous affection
is varied toward different characters. Sympathy
can never explain the immediate ardour of our good-will
towards the morally excellent character, or the eagerness
of a dying man for the prosperity of his children and
friends. Having thus accepted the existence of
purely disinterested affections, and divided them
as before into calm and turbulent, he puts the question,
Whether is the selfish or benevolent principle to yield
in case of opposition? And although it appears
that, as a fact, the universal happiness is preferred
to the individual in the order of the world by the
Deity, this is nothing, unless by some determination
of the soul we are made to comply with the Divine
intentions. If by the desire of reward, it is
selfishness still; if by the desire, following upon
the sight, of moral excellence, then there must necessarily
exist as its object some determination of the will
involving supreme moral excellence, otherwise there
will be no way of deciding between particular affections.
This leads on to the consideration of the Moral Faculty.
But, in the beginning of Chapter IV., he first rejects
one by one these various accounts of the reason of
our approbation of moral conduct:—pleasure
by sympathy; pleasure through the moral sense; notion
of advantage to the agent, or to the approver, and
this direct or imagined; tendency to procure honour;
conformity to law, to truth, fitness, congruity, &c.;
also education, association, &c. He then asserts
a natural and immediate determination in man to approve
certain affections and actions consequent on them;
or a natural sense of immediate excellence in them,
not referred to any other quality perceivable by our
other senses, or by reasoning. It is a sense not
dependent on bodily organs, but a settled determination
of the soul. It is a sense, in like manner as,
with every one of our powers—voice, designing,
motion, reasoning, there is bound up a taste, sense,
or relish, discerning and recommending their proper
exercise; but superior to all these, because the power