who practised all manner of secret vices, and whose
behaviour was in outrageous contradiction to their
creed of the “absence of emotions.”
There were not only many Honeymans, there were many
Stigginses. There were idlers and vagabonds on
a level with the mendicant friars and pardon-sellers
of the time of Chaucer. There were pompous hypocrites.
Also side by side with the serious and earnest philosopher,
as deeply learned in the books of his sect as a modern
divine, there were charlatans and dabblers. It
is unfortunately in this last light that the Apostle
Paul appeared to the professional Stoic and Epicurean
teachers of Athens. They were the finished products
of the philosophic schools of the most famous universities,
while he was supposed by them to be teaching some new
kind of philosophy. Philosophers were apt to
be itinerant, and St. Paul was looked upon as but
another of these new arrivals. In his language
they detected what seemed to be borrowed notions not
consistently bound together, and they therefore called
him by a name which it is not easy to translate.
Literally it is “a picker up of seeds”—that
is to say, a sciolist who gathers scraps from profounder
people and gives them out with an air. Perhaps
the nearest, although an undignified, word is “quack.”
That Paul possessed a knowledge of Greek philosophy,
and particularly of Stoicism, is practically certain.
He came from Tarsus in Cilicia, and Cilicia was the
native home of many leading Stoics, including its
greatest representative in all antiquity. He had
been taught by Gamaliel, who was versed in “the
learning of the Greeks.” His address at
Athens was deliberately meant to bear a relation to
the philosophy of the experts who were present, but
necessarily it could only introduce a few salient
allusions, such as even a dabbler could have picked
up, and we can hardly blame the specialists for their
erroneous judgment. As he says himself: “The
Greeks demand philosophy; but we proclaim a Messiah
crucified, to the Jews a stumbling-block, and to the
Greeks a folly.”
To discuss further the moral ideas of the Roman world
would consume more space and time than can be afforded
here. It may, however, be worth while to mention
that suicide was commonly—and especially
by the Stoics—looked upon as a natural
and blameless thing, when calm reason appeared to
justify the proceeding, and when due consideration
was given to social claims. To seek a euthanasia
in such cases was an act of wisdom. Belief in
an underworld or an after life was not rare among
the common people, but it certainly did not exist in
any force among the cultivated classes. It was
taught neither by philosophy nor by the religion of
the state. Yet the sense that rewards or punishments
are unfairly meted out in this world was strong in
many a mind, and this is one of the facts which account
for the hold taken upon such minds, first by the religion
of Isis, and then in a still greater and more abiding
measure by Christianity.