does not make us deny that the steam-engine and microscope
owe their development to design. If each step
of the road was designed, the whole journey was designed,
though the particular end was not designed when the
journey was begun. And so is it, according to
the older view of evolution, with the development
of those living organs, or machines, that are born
with us, as part of the perambulating carpenter’s
chest we call our bodies. The older view gives
us our design, and gives us our evolution too.
If it refuses to see a quasi-anthropomorphic God
modelling each species from without as a potter models
clay, it gives us God as vivifying and indwelling
in all His creatures—He in them, and they
in Him. If it refuses to see God outside the
universe, it equally refuses to see any part of the
universe as outside God. If it makes the universe
the body of God, it also makes God the soul of the
universe. The question at issue, then, between
the Darwinism of Erasmus Darwin and the neo-Darwinism
of his grandson, is not a personal one, nor anything
like a personal one. It not only involves the
existence of evolution, but it affects the view we
take of life and things in an endless variety of most
interesting and important ways. It is imperative,
therefore, on those who take any interest in these
matters, to place side by side in the clearest contrast
the views of those who refer the evolution of species
mainly to accumulation of variations that have no
other inception than chance, and of that older school
which makes design perceive and develop still further
the goods that chance provides.
But over and above this, which would be in itself
sufficient, the historical mode of studying any question
is the only one which will enable us to comprehend
it effectually. The personal element cannot
be eliminated from the consideration of works written
by living persons for living persons. We want
to know who is who—whom we can depend upon
to have no other end than the making things clear to
himself and his readers, and whom we should mistrust
as having an ulterior aim on which he is more intent
than on the furthering of our better understanding.
We want to know who is doing his best to help us,
and who is only trying to make us help him, or to bolster
up the system in which his interests are vested.
There is nothing that will throw more light upon
these points than the way in which a man behaves towards
those who have worked in the same field with himself,
and, again, than his style. A man’s style,
as Buffon long since said, is the man himself.
By style, I do not, of course, mean grammar or rhetoric,
but that style of which Buffon again said that it
is like happiness, and vient de la douceur de l’ame.
When we find a man concealing worse than nullity
of meaning under sentences that sound plausibly enough,
we should distrust him much as we should a fellow-traveller
whom we caught trying to steal our watch. We
often cannot judge of the truth or falsehood of facts
for ourselves, but we most of us know enough of human
nature to be able to tell a good witness from a bad
one.