III. Concrete Relational Concepts (still more
abstract, yet not
entirely devoid of a measure
of concreteness): normally expressed by
affixing non-radical elements
to radical elements, but generally at
a greater remove from these
than is the case with elements of type
II, or by inner modification
of radical elements; differ
fundamentally from type II
in indicating or implying relations that
transcend the particular word
to which they are immediately
attached, thus leading over
to
IV. Pure Relational Concepts (purely
abstract): normally expressed by
affixing non-radical elements
to radical elements (in which case
these concepts are frequently
intertwined with those of type III) or
by their inner modification,
by independent words, or by position;
serve to relate the concrete
elements of the proposition to each
other, thus giving it definite
syntactic form.
[Footnote 64: Except, of course, the fundamental selection and contrast necessarily implied in defining one concept as against another. “Man” and “white” possess an inherent relation to “woman” and “black,” but it is a relation of conceptual content only and is of no direct interest to grammar.]
[Footnote 65: Thus, the _-er_ of farmer may he defined as indicating that particular substantive concept (object or thing) that serves as the habitual subject of the particular verb to which it is affixed. This relation of “subject” (a farmer farms) is inherent in and specific to the word; it does not exist for the sentence as a whole. In the same way the _-ling_ of duckling defines a specific relation of attribution that concerns only the radical element, not the sentence.]
The nature of these four classes of concepts as regards
their
concreteness or their power to express syntactic relations
may be thus
symbolized:
_
Material _/ I. Basic Concepts
Content \_ II. Derivational
Concepts
_
Relation _/ III. Concrete
Relational Concepts
\_
IV. Pure Relational Concepts
These schemes must not be worshipped as fetiches. In the actual work of analysis difficult problems frequently arise and we may well be in doubt as to how to group a given set of concepts. This is particularly apt to be the case in exotic languages, where we may be quite sure of the analysis of the words in a sentence and yet not succeed in acquiring that inner “feel” of its structure that enables us to tell infallibly what is “material content” and what is “relation.” Concepts of class I are essential to all speech, also concepts of class IV. Concepts II and III are both common, but not essential; particularly group III, which represents, in effect, a psychological and formal confusion of types II and IV or of types I and IV, is an avoidable class of concepts.