virtue; and this object they seek to attain by prescribing
to human life fixed principles of action, fixed rules
of conduct. In its uninspired as well as in its
inspired moments, in its days of languor and gloom
as well as in its days of sunshine and energy, human
life has thus always a clue to follow, and may always
be making way towards its goal. Christian morality
has not failed to supply to human life aids of this
sort. It has supplied them far more abundantly
than many of its critics imagine. The most exquisite
document after those of the New Testament, of all
the documents the Christian spirit has ever inspired,—the
Imitation,[184]—by no means contains
the whole of Christian morality; nay, the disparagers
of this morality would think themselves sure of triumphing
if one agreed to look for it in the
Imitation
only. But even the
Imitation is full of
passages like these: “Vita sine proposito
languida et vaga est";—“Omni die renovare
debemus propositum nostrum, dicentes: nunc hodie
perfecte incipiamus, quia nihil est quod hactenus
fecimus";—“Secundum propositum nostrum
est cursus profectus nostri";—“Raro
etiam unum vitium perfecte vincimus, et ad
quotidianum
profectum non accendimur”; “Semper aliquid
certi proponendum est”; “Tibi ipsi violentiam
frequenter fac.” (
A life without a purpose
is a languid, drifting thing;—Every day
we ought to renew our purpose, saying to ourselves:
This day let us make a sound beginning, for what we
have hitherto done is nought;—Our improvement
is in proportion to our purpose;—We hardly
ever manage to get completely rid even of one fault,
and do not set our hearts on daily_ improvement;—Always
place a definite purpose before thee;—Get
the habit of mastering thine inclination._) These
are moral precepts, and moral precepts of the best
kind. As rules to hold possession of our conduct,
and to keep us in the right course through outward
troubles and inward perplexity, they are equal to
the best ever furnished by the great masters of morals—Epictetus
and Marcus Aurelius.
But moral rules, apprehended as ideas first, and then
rigorously followed as laws, are, and must be, for
the sage only. The mass of mankind have neither
force of intellect enough to apprehend them clearly
as ideas, nor force of character enough to follow them
strictly as laws. The mass of mankind can be
carried along a course full of hardship for the natural
man, can be borne over the thousand impediments of
the narrow way, only by the tide of a joyful and bounding
emotion. It is impossible to rise from reading
Epictetus[185]or Marcus Aurelius without a sense of
constraint and melancholy, without feeling that the
burden laid upon man is well-nigh greater than he can
bear. Honor to the sages who have felt this,
and yet have borne it! Yet, even for the sage,
this sense of labor and sorrow in his march towards
the goal constitutes a relative inferiority; the noblest
souls of whatever creed, the pagan Empedocles[186]