leads to disorder, commotions, and evils far more insufferable
than those which they pretend to remedy."[5] Now,
Sir, this principle would carry Europe back again,
at once, into the middle of the Dark Ages. It
is the old doctrine of the Divine right of kings, advanced
now by new advocates, and sustained by a formidable
array of power. That the people hold their fundamental
privileges as matter of concession or indulgence from
the sovereign power, is a sentiment not easy to be
diffused in this age, any farther than it is enforced
by the direct operation of military means. It
is true, certainly, that some six centuries ago the
early founders of English liberty called the instrument
which secured their rights a
charter.
It was, indeed, a concession; they had obtained it
sword in hand from the king; and in many other cases,
whatever was obtained, favorable to human rights,
from the tyranny and despotism of the feudal sovereigns,
was called by the names of
privileges and
liberties,
as being matter of special favor. Though we retain
this language at the present time, the principle itself
belongs to ages that have long passed by us.
The civilized world has done with “the enormous
faith, of many made for one.” Society asserts
its own rights, and alleges them to be original, sacred,
and unalienable. It is not satisfied with having
kind masters; it demands a participation in its own
government; and in states much advanced in civilization,
it urges this demand with a constancy and an energy
that cannot well nor long be resisted. There
are, happily, enough of regulated governments in the
world, and those among the most distinguished, to operate
as constant examples, and to keep alive an unceasing
panting in the bosoms of men for the enjoyment of
similar free institutions.
When the English Revolution of 1688 took place, the
English people did not content themselves with the
example of Runnymede; they did not build their hopes
upon royal charters; they did not, like the authors
of the Laybach circular, suppose that all useful changes
in constitutions and laws must proceed from those
only whom God has rendered responsible for power.
They were somewhat better instructed in the principles
of civil liberty, or at least they were better lovers
of those principles than the sovereigns of Laybach.
Instead of petitioning for charters, they declared
their rights, and while they offered to the Prince
of Orange the crown with one hand, they held in the
other an enumeration of those privileges which they
did not profess to hold as favors, but which they
demanded and insisted upon as their undoubted rights.
I need not stop to observe, Mr. Chairman, how totally
hostile are these doctrines of Laybach to the fundamental
principles of our government. They are in direct
contradiction; the principles of good and evil are
hardly more opposite. If these principles of the
sovereigns be true, we are but in a state of rebellion
or of anarchy, and are only tolerated among civilized
states because it has not yet been convenient to reduce
us to the true standard.