which is itself only an accident of nature—is
mere caprice like the former. That one
is therefore only a despot, not a free man.
The consciousness of freedom first arose among the
Greeks, and therefore they were free; but they, and
the Romans likewise, knew only that some are
free, not man as such. Even Plato and Aristotle
did not know this. The Greeks, therefore, had
slaves, and their whole life and the maintenance of
their splendid liberty was implicated with the institution
of slavery—a fact, moreover, which made
that liberty, on the one hand, only an accidental,
transient and limited growth, and on the other, a
rigorous thraldom of our common nature—of
the Human. The Germanic nations, under the influence
of Christianity, were the first to attain the consciousness
that man is free; that it is the freedom of Spirit
which constitutes its essence. This consciousness
arose first in religion, the inmost region of Spirit;
but to introduce the principle into the various relations
of the actual world involves a more extensive problem
than its simple implantation—a problem whose
solution and application require a severe and lengthened
process of culture. In proof of this we may note
that slavery did not cease immediately on the reception
of Christianity. Still less did liberty predominate
in States; or governments and constitutions adopt
a rational organization, or recognize freedom as their
basis. That application of the principle to political
relations, the thorough molding and interpenetration
of the constitution of society by it, is a process
identical with history itself. I have already
directed attention to the distinction here involved,
between a principle as such and its application—that
is, its introduction and fulfilment in the actual
phenomena of Spirit and life. This is a point
of fundamental importance in our science, and one which
must be constantly respected as essential. And
in the same way as this distinction has attracted
attention in view of the Christian principle of self-consciousness—freedom,
it also shows itself as an essential one in view of
the principle of freedom generally. The history
of the world is none other than the progress of the
consciousness of freedom—progress whose
development, according to the necessity of its nature,
it is our business to investigate.
The general statement given above of the various grades in the consciousness of freedom-which we applied in the first instance to the fact that the Eastern nations knew only that one is free, the Greek and Roman world only that some are free, while we know that all men absolutely (man as man) are free—supplies us with the natural division of universal history, and suggests the mode of its discussion. This is remarked, however, only incidentally and anticipatively; some other ideas must be first explained.