expression even, of communication between man and
man, on the hypothesis of any radical difference in
the experience and faculties to which all expression
appeals for its intelligibility; neither could there
be any system of life in social groups, or plan for
education, unless such a common basis is accepted.
The postulate of a common human nature is analogous
to that of the unity of matter in science; it finds
its complete expression in the doctrine of the brotherhood
of man, for if race be fundamentally distinguished
from race as was once thought, it is only as element
is distinguished from element in the old chemistry.
So, too, the postulate of an order obtaining in the
soul, universal and necessary, independent of man’s
volition, analogous in all respects to the order of
nature, is parallel with that of the constancy of
physical law. A rational life expects this order.
The first knowledge of it comes to us, as that of
natural law, by experience; in the social world—the
relations of men to one another—and in
the more important region of our own nature we learn
the issue of certain courses of action as well as in
the external world; in our own lives and in our dealings
with others we come to a knowledge of, and a conformity
to, the conditions under which we live, the laws operant
in our being, as well as those of the physical world.
Literature assumes this order; in Aeschylus, Cervantes,
or Shakspere, it is this that gives their work interest.
Apart from natural science, the whole authority of
the past in its entire accumulation of wisdom rests
upon the permanence of this order, and its capacity
to be known by man; that virtue makes men noble and
vice renders them base, is a statement without meaning
unless this order is continuous through ages; all principles
of action, all schemes of culture, would be uncertain
except on this foundation.
So near is this order to us that it was known long
before science came to any maturity. We have
added, in truth, little to our knowledge of humanity
since the Greeks; and if one wonders why ethics came
before science, let him own at least that its priority
shows that it is near and vital in life as science
is not. We can do, it seems, without Kepler’s
laws, but not without the Decalogue. The race
acquires first what is most needful for life; and
man’s heart was always with him, and his fate
near. A second reason, it may be noted, for the
later development of science is that our senses, as
used by science, are more mental now, and the object
itself is observable only by the intervention of the
mind through the telescope or microscope or a hundred
instruments into which, though physical, the mind
enters. Our methods, too, as well as our instruments,
are things of the mind. It behooves us to remember
in an age which science is commonly thought to have
materialized, that more and more the mind enters into
all results, and fills an ever larger place in life;
and this should serve to make materialism seem more