to die. The people might not be ready to overthrow
Louis Philippe, to give his place to Louis Napoleon,
but it did not follow that they would have seen the
latter’s execution with satisfaction, because
they desired peace, and he had fallen into the habit
of breaking it. The enthusiasm that was created
in France by the arrival in that country of the remains
of Napoleon I., not three months after the coming
Napoleon III. had been sent to the fortress of Ham,
showed how difficult a matter it would have been to
proceed capitally against the Prince. Louis Philippe
has been praised for sparing him; but the praise is
undeserved. Certainly, the King of the French
was not a cruel man, and it was with sincere regret
that he signed the death-warrants of men who had sought
his own life, and who had murdered his friends; but
it would have been no act of cruelty, had he sent
his rival to the guillotine. When a man makes
a throw for a crown, he accepts what is staked, against
it,—a coffin. Nothing is better established
than this, that, when a sovereign is assailed, the
intention of the assailant being his overthrow, that
sovereign has a perfect right to put his rival to
death, if he succeed in obtaining possession of his
person. The most confirmed believer in Richard
III.’s demoniac character would not think of
adding the execution of Richmond to his crimes, had
Plantagenet, and not Tudor, triumphed on Bosworth
Field. James II. has never been blamed for causing
Monmouth to be put to death, but for having complied
with his nephew’s request for a personal interview,
at which he refused to grant his further request for
a mitigation of punishment. Murat’s death
was an unnecessary act, but Ferdinand of Naples has
never been censured for it. Had Louis Philippe
followed these examples, and those of a hundred similar
cases, he could not have been charged with undue severity
in the exercise of his power for the conservation
of his own rights, and the maintenance of the tranquillity,
not of France alone, but of Europe, and of the world,
which the triumph of a Bonaparte might have perilled.
He spared the future Emperor’s life, not from
any considerations of a chivalric character, but because
he durst not take it. He feared that the blood
of the offender would more than atone for his offence,
and he would not throw into the political caldron
so rich a material, dreading the effects of its presence
there. Then the Orleans party and the Imperial
party not only marched with each other, but often crossed
and ran into each other; and it was not safe to run
the risk of offending the first by an attempt to punish
its occasional ally. There was, too, something
of the ludicrous in the Boulogne affair, which enabled
government to regard the chief offender with cheap
compassion. Louis Philippe is entitled to no
credit, on the score of mercy, for his conduct in
1840,—for the decision of the Court of Peers
was his inspiration; but he acted wisely,—so
wisely, that, if he had done as well in 1848, his
grandson would at this moment have been King of the
French, and the Emperor that is a wanderer, with nothing
but a character for flightiness and a capacity for
failure to distinguish him from the herd, while many
would have regarded him as a madman. But the end
was not then, and the hand of Fate was not even near
that curtain which was to be raised for the disclosure
of events destined to shake and to change the world.