to have been implanted in the mind by God Himself,
and endowed by Him with the unique prerogative of
infallibility. Even so philosophical and sober
a writer as Bishop Butler has given some countenance
to this extravagant supposition, and to the exaggerated
language which he employs on the prerogatives of conscience,
and to the emphatic manner in which he insists on the
absolute, if not the infallible, character of its
decisions, may be traced much of the misconception
which still prevails on the subject. But we have
only to take account of the notorious fact that the
consciences of two equally conscientious men may point
in entirely opposite directions, in order to see that
the decisions of conscience cannot, at all events,
be credited with infallibility. Those who denounce
and those who defend religious persecution, those
who insist on the removal and those who insist on the
retention of religious disabilities, those who are
in favour of and those who are opposed to a relaxation
of the marriage laws, those who advocate a total abstention
from intoxicating liquors and those who allow of a
moderate use of them,—men on both sides
in these controversies, or, at least, the majority
of them, doubtless act conscientiously, and yet, as
they arrive at opposite conclusions, the conscience
of one side or other must be at fault. There is
no act of religious persecution, there are few acts
of political or personal cruelty, for which the authority
of conscience might not be invoked. I doubt not
that Queen Mary acted as conscientiously in burning
the Reformers as they did in promulgating their opinions
or we do in condemning her acts. It is plain,
then, not only that the decisions of conscience are
not infallible, but that they must, to a very large
extent, be relative to the circumstances and opinions
of those who form them. In any intelligible or
tenable sense of the term, conscience stands simply
for the aggregate of our moral opinions reinforced
by the moral sanction of self-approbation or self-disapprobation.
That we ought to act in accordance with these opinions,
and that we are acting wrongly if we act in opposition
to them, is a truism. ‘Follow Conscience’
is the only safe guide, when the moment of action
has arrived. But it is equally important to insist
on the fallibility of conscience, and to urge men,
by all means in their power, to be constantly improving
and instructing their consciences, or, in plain words,
to review and, wherever occasion offers, to correct
their conceptions of right and wrong. The ‘plain,
honest man’ of Bishop Butler would, undoubtedly,
always follow his conscience, but it is by no means
certain that his conscience would always guide him
rightly, and it is quite certain that it would often
prompt him differently from the consciences of other
‘plain, honest men’ trained elsewhere and
under other circumstances. To act contrary to
our opinions of right and wrong would be treason to
our moral nature, but it does not follow that those
opinions are not susceptible of improvement and correction,
or that it is not as much our duty to take pains to
form true opinions as to act in accordance with our
opinions when we have formed them.