its force generally, and, before we expose men to
this danger, we ought to have some adequate justification.
But there is also the speculative ground that any
given society, and indeed mankind generally, has been
engaged for ages in feeling its way, instinctively
or semi-consciously, towards a solution of the self-same
problems which the philosopher is attempting to solve
consciously and of set purpose. That, on the whole,
a society has solved these problems in the manner best
suited to its existing needs and circumstances may
fairly be taken for granted, and, even where the ethical
stand-point of the reformer is very superior to the
stand-point of the society which he wishes to reform,
he will be wise in endeavouring to introduce his reforms
gradually, and, if possible, in connexion with principles
already acknowledged, rather than in attempting to
effect a moral revolution, the ultimate results of
which it may be impossible to foresee. The work
of the moralist is, therefore, best regarded as corrective
of, and supplementary to, the work which mankind is
constantly doing for itself, and not as antagonistic
to it. The method is the same in both cases:
only it is applied semi-consciously, and merely as
occasions suggest it, in the one case; consciously
and spontaneously in the other. In both cases
alike the guiding principle, whether of action or
of speculation upon action, is the adaptation of conduct
to surrounding circumstances, physical and social,
with a view to promote, to the utmost extent possible,
the well-being of the individual and of the society
of which he is a member. Where the interests
of the individual and of the society clash, society,
that is to say, a man’s fellow-citizens, usually
approves, as we saw in the last chapter, of the sacrifice
of individual to social interests, a course of conduct
which is also, on reflexion, usually stamped by the
individual’s own approbation, and hence we may
say briefly that their tendency to promote or impair
the welfare of society is the test by which, in different
ways, all actions are estimated alike by the philosopher,
in his hours of speculation, and by the community at
large, in the practical work of life.
In laying down the principle that the presumption
of the moralist should always be in favour of existing
rules of conduct, I intimated that there was one exception
to this principle. The exception includes all
those cases which are legitimate, though not obvious,
applications of existing rules, and to which, therefore,
the ordinary moral sentiment does not attach in the
same way that it does to the plainer and more direct
applications. Thus, if it can be shewn, as it
undoubtedly can be, that smuggling falls under the
head of stealing, and holding out false hopes under
that of lying, the moralist need take no account of
the lax moral sentiment which exists with regard to
these practices, though, of course, in estimating
the guilt of the individual as distinct from the character
of the act, due allowance must be made for his imperfect
appreciation of the moral bearings of his conduct.
This exception, as will be found in the next chapter,
covers, and therefore at once justifies, a large proportion
of the criticisms which, in the present advanced stage
of morality, when the more fundamental principles have
been already settled, it is still open to us to make.