contrary to what we then supposed to be right leaves
behind it a trace of dissatisfaction and pain, which
may, at any future time, reappear to trouble and distress
us; just as to have acted, in spite of all conflicting
considerations, in a manner which we then conceived
to be right, may, in after years, be a perennial source
of pleasure and satisfaction. It is characteristic
of the pleasures and pains of reflexion on our past
acts (which pleasures and pains of reflexion may,
of course, connect themselves with other than purely
moral considerations), not only that they admit of
being more intense than any other pleasures and pains,
but that, whenever there is any conflict between the
moral sanction and any other sanction, it is to the
moral sanction that they attach themselves. Thus,
if a man has incurred physical suffering, or braved
the penalties of the law or the ill word of society,
in pursuance of a course of conduct which he deemed
to be right, he looks back upon his actions with satisfaction,
and the more important the actions, and the clearer
his convictions of right and the stronger the inducements
to act otherwise, the more intense will his satisfaction
be. But no such satisfaction is felt, when a man
has sacrificed his convictions of right to avoid physical
pain, or to escape the penalties of the law, or to
conciliate the goodwill of society; the feeling, on
the other hand, will be that of dissatisfaction with
himself, varying, according to circumstances, from
regret to remorse. And, if no similar remark
has to be made with reference to the religious sanction,
it is because, in all the higher forms of religion,
the religious sanction is conceived of as applying
to exactly the same actions as the moral sanction.
What a man himself deems right, that he conceives
God to approve of, and what he conceives God as disapproving
of, that he deems wrong. But in a religion in
which God was not regarded as holy, just, and true,
or in which there was a plurality of gods, some good
and some evil, I conceive that a man would look back
with satisfaction, and not with dissatisfaction, on
those acts in which he had followed his own sense
of right rather than the supposed will of the Deity,
just as, when there is a conflict between the two,
he now congratulates himself on having submitted to
the claims of conscience rather than to those of the
law.
The justification, then, of that claim to superiority, which is asserted by the moral sanction, consists, I conceive, in two circumstances: first, that the pleasures and pains, the feelings of satisfaction and dissatisfaction, of self-approbation and self-disapprobation, by means of which it works, are, in the normally constituted mind, far more intense and durable than any other pleasures and pains; secondly, that, whenever this sanction comes into conflict with any other sanction, its defeat is sure, on a careful retrospect of our acts, to bring regret or remorse, whereas its victory is equally certain to bring pleasure and satisfaction.