wisdom of popularly elected chambers.” We
are not surprised at the misgiving. But after
reasonable attention to facts, we cannot recall any
publicist, whom it could be worth while to spend five
minutes in refuting, who has ever said that popularly
elected chambers are absolutely wise. Again, we
should like the evidence for the statement that popularly
elected Houses “do not nowadays appeal to the
wise deduction from experience, as old as Aristotle,
which no student of constitutional history will deny,
that the best constitutions are those in which there
is a large popular element. It is a singular
proof of the widespread influence of the speculations
of Rousseau that although very few First Chambers really
represent the entire community, nevertheless in Europe
they almost invariably claim to reflect it, and as
a consequence they assume an air of divinity, which
if it rightfully belonged to them would be fatal to
all argument for a Second Chamber.” That
would be very important If it were true. But
is it true that First Chambers assume an air of divinity?
Or is such an expression a “burlesque of the
real argument?” A reasonable familiarity with
the course of the controversy in France, where the
discussion has been abundant, and in England, where
it has been comparatively meagre, leaves me, for one,
entirely ignorant that this claim for divinity, or
anything like it, is ever heard in the debate.
The most powerful modern champion of popular government
was Gambetta. Did Gambetta consider First Chambers
divine? On the contrary, some of the most strenuous
pleas for the necessity of a Second Chamber are to
be found precisely in the speeches of Gambetta (
e.g.
his speech at Grenoble, in the autumn of 1878,
Discours
viii. 270,
etc.). Abstract thinking is thinking
withdrawn from the concrete and particular facts.
But the abstract thinker should not withdraw too far.
Sir Henry Maine speaks (p. 185) of “the saner
political theorist, who holds that in secular matters
it is better to walk by sight than by faith.”
He allows that a theorist of this kind, as regards
popularly elected chambers, “will be satisfied
that experience has shown the best Constitutions to
be those in which the popular element is large, and
he will readily admit that, as the structure of each
society of men slowly alters, it is well to alter
and amend the organisation by which this element makes
itself felt.” Sir Henry Maine would surely
have done better service in this grave and difficult
discussion, if he had dealt with views which he mistrusts,
as they are really held and expressed by sane theorists,
and not by insane theorists out of sight. In
France, a hundred years ago, from causes that are capable
of explanation, the democracy of sentiment swept away
the democracy of utility. In spite of casual
phrases in public discussion, and in spite of the
incendiary trash of Red journalists without influence,
it is the democracy of reason, experience, and utility
that is now in the ascendant, both in France and elsewhere.