there for them; and, lastly, that he should descend
again at the end of the world to judge the whole human
race, on which occasion all that were in their
graves should hear his voice and come forth, they
that had done good unto the resurrection of life,
and they that had done evil unto the resurrection
of damnation,—if this person made these
assertions about himself, and all that was done
was to make the assertions, what would be the
inevitable conclusion of sober reason respecting that
person? The necessary conclusion of sober reason
respecting that person would be that he was disordered
in his understanding. What other decision
could we come to when a man, looking like one of
ourselves, and only exemplifying in his life and circumstances
the ordinary course of nature, said this about
himself, but that when reason had lost its balance
a dream of extraordinary and unearthly grandeur
might be the result? By no rational being could
a just and benevolent life be accepted as proof
of such astonishing announcements. Miracles
are the necessary complement then of the truth
of such announcements, which without them are purposeless
and abortive, the unfinished fragments of a design
which is nothing unless it is the whole. They
are necessary to the justification of such announcements,
which, indeed, unless they are supernatural truths,
are the wildest delusions. The matter and its
guarantee are the two parts of a revelation, the absence
of either of which neutralises and undoes it.
A revelation, in any sense in which it is more than
merely a result of the natural progress of the human
mind and the gradual clearing up of mistakes, cannot
in the nature of things be without miracles, because
it is not merely a discovery of ideas and rules of
life, but of facts undiscoverable without it.
It involves constituent miracles, to use De
Quincey’s phrase, as part of its substance, and
could not claim a bearing without evidential
or polemic ones. No other portion or form
of proof, however it may approve itself to the ideas
of particular periods or minds, can really make up
for this. The alleged sinlessness of the Teacher,
the internal evidence from adaptation to human nature,
the historical argument of the development of Christendom,
are, as Mr. Mozley points out, by themselves inadequate,
without that further guarantee which is contained
in miracles, to prove the Divine origin of a religion.
The tendency has been of late to fall back on these
attractive parts of the argument, which admit of such
varied handling and expression, and come home so naturally
to the feelings of an age so busy and so keen in pursuing
the secrets of human character, and so fascinated
with its unfolding wonders. But take any of them,
the argument from results, for instance, perhaps the
most powerful of them all. “We cannot,”
as Mr. Mozley says, “rest too much upon it, so
long as we do not charge it with more of the burden
of proof than it is in its own nature equal to—viz.