as it has come rather of too much matter than too
little; while his teaching, far from being that of
a facile “Epicureanism,” is seen, properly
understood, to involve something like the austerity
of a fastidious Puritanism, and to result in a jealous
asceticism of the senses rather than in their indulgence.
“Slight as was the burden of positive moral obligation
with which he had entered Rome,” he writes of
Marius, as on his first evening in Rome the murmur
comes to him of “the lively, reckless call to
‘play,’ from the sons and daughters of
foolishness,” “it was to no wasteful and
vagrant affections, such as these, that his Epicureanism
had committed him.” Such warnings against
misunderstanding Pater is careful to place, at, so
to say, all the cross-roads in his books, so scrupulously
concerned is he lest any reader should take the wrong
turning. Few writers, indeed, manifest so constant
a consideration for, and, in minor matters, such a
sensitive courtesy toward, their readers, while in
matters of conscience Pater seems to feel for them
an actual pastoral responsibility. His well-known
withdrawal of the “Conclusion” to
The
Renaissance from its second edition, from a fear
that “it might possibly mislead some of those
young men into whose hands it might fall,” is
but one of many examples of his solicitude; and surely
such as have gone astray after such painstaking guidance
have but their own natures to blame. As he justly
says, again of Marius, “in the reception of
metaphysical
formula, all depends, as regards
their actual and ulterior result, on the pre-existent
qualities of that soil of human nature into which
they fall—the company they find already
present there, on their admission into the house of
thought.”
That Pater’s philosophy could ever have been
misunderstood is not to be entertained with patience
by any one who has read him with even ordinary attention;
that it may have been misapplied, in spite of all his
care, is, of course, possible; but if a writer is
to be called to account for all the misapplications,
or distortions, of his philosophy, writing may as
well come to an end. Yet, inconceivable as it
may sound, a critic very properly held in popular
esteem recently gave it as his opinion that the teaching
of Walter Pater was responsible for the tragic career
of the author of The Picture of Dorian Gray.
Certainly that remarkable man was an “epicurean”—but
one, to quote Meredith, “whom Epicurus would
have scourged out of his garden”; and the statement
made by the critic in question that The Renaissance
is the book referred to in The Picture of Dorian
Gray as having had a sinister influence over its
hero is so easily disposed of by a reference to that
romance itself that it is hard to understand its ever
having been made. Here is the passage describing
the demoralizing book in question: