as phrases, or as sentences, and not as
cases.
They no more take the nature of cases, than they become
nouns or pronouns. Yet Nixon, by assuming that
of, with the word governed by it, constitutes
a
possessive case, contrives to give to participles,
and even to the infinitive mood,
all three of the
cases. Of the infinitive, he says, “An
examination of the first and second methods of parsing
this mood, must naturally lead to the inference that
it is a substantive; and that, if it has the
nominative case, it must also have the possessive and
objective cases of a substantive. The fourth
method proves its [capacity of] being in the possessive
case: thus, ‘A desire
to learn;’
that is, ‘
of learning.’ When
it follows a participle, or a verb, as by the fifth
or [the] seventh method, it is in the objective case.
Method sixth is analogous to the Case Absolute of
a substantive.”—
Nixon’s Parser,
p. 83. If the infinitive mood is really a
declinable
substantive, none of our grammarians have placed
it in the right chapter; except that bold contemner
of all grammatical and literary authority, Oliver
B. Peirce. When will the cause of learning cease
to have assailants and underminers among those who
profess to serve it? Thus every new grammatist,
has some grand absurdity or other, peculiar to himself;
and what can be more gross, than to talk of English
infinitives and participles as being in the
possessive
case?
OBS. 3.—It was long a subject of dispute
among the grammarians, what number of cases an English
noun should be supposed to have. Some, taking
the Latin language for their model, and turning certain
phrases into cases to fill up the deficits, were for
having six in each number; namely, the nominative,
the genitive, the dative, the accusative, the vocative,
and the ablative. Others, contending that a case
in grammar could be nothing else than a terminational
inflection, and observing that English nouns have but
one case that differs from the nominative in form,
denied that there were more than two, the nominative
and the possessive. This was certainly an important
question, touching a fundamental principle of our grammar;
and any erroneous opinion concerning it, might well
go far to condemn the book that avouched it.
Every intelligent teacher must see this. For what
sense could be made of parsing, without supposing
an objective case to nouns? or what propriety could
there be in making the words, of, and to,
and from, govern or compose three different
cases? Again, with what truth can it be said,
that nouns have no cases in English? or what
reason can be assigned for making more than three?