at school and college. But there were two great
defects in it. First, as Professor Wilkins points
out, the subjects of declamation were too often out
of all relation to real life,
e.g. taken from
the Greek mythology; or if less barren than usual,
were far more commonplace and flat than those of our
debating societies. To harangue on the question
whether the life of a lawyer or a soldier is the best,
is hardly so inspiring as to debate a question of the
day about Ireland or India, which educates in living
fact as well as in the rules of the orator’s
art. Secondly, the whole aim and object of this
“finishing” portion of a boy’s education
was a false one. Even the excellent Quintilian,
the best of all Roman teachers, believed that the
statesman (civilis vir) and the orator are identical:
that the statesman must be vir bonus because the vir
bonus makes the best orator; that he should be sapiens
for the same reason.[302] And the object of oratory
is “id agere, ut iudici quae proposita fuerint,
vera et honesta
videantur":[303]
i.e. the
object is not truth, but persuasion. We might
get an idea of how such a training would fail in forming
character, if we could imagine all our liberal education
subordinated to the practice of journalism. But
fortunately for us, in this scientific age, words
and the use of words no longer serve as the basis
of education or as the chief nurture of young life.
We need to see facts, to understand causes, to distinguish
objective truth from truth reflected in books.
But the perfect education must be a skilful mingling
of the two methods; and it may be as well to take care
that we do not lose contact with the best thoughts
of the best men, because they are contained in the
literature we show some signs of neglecting.
We may say of science what Cicero said of rhetoric,
that it cannot do without sapientia.
Of schools of philosophy I have already said something
in the last chapter, and as the study of philosophy
was hardly a part of the regular curriculum of education
properly so called, I shall pass it over here.
The philosopher was usually to be found in wealthy
houses, and if he were a wholesome person, and not
a Philodemus, he might assuredly exercise a good influence
on a young man. Or a youth might go to Athens
or Rhodes or to some other Greek city, to attend the
lectures of some famous professor. Cicero heard
Phaedrus the Epicurean at Rome and then Philo the
Academician, who had a lasting influence on his pupil,
and then, at the age of twenty-seven, went to Greece
for two years, studying at Athens, Rhodes, and elsewhere.
Caesar also went to Rhodes, and he and Cicero both
attended the lectures of Molo in rhetoric, in which
study, as well as in philosophy, lectures were to
be heard in all the great Greek cities.[304] Cicero
sent his own son to “the University in Athens”
at the age of twenty, giving him an ample allowance
and doubtless much good advice. The young man
soon outran his allowance and got into debt; the good
advice he seems to have failed to utilise, and in
fact gave his father considerable anxiety.