the spirit cognizes sensuous relations by means of
the pure, archetypal, intellectual relations born
in it, which, before the advent of sense-impressions,
have lain concealed behind the veil of possibility;
inclination and aversion between men, their delight
in beauty, the pleasant impression of a view, depend
upon an unconscious and instinctive perception of
proportions. This quantitative view of the world,
which, with a consciousness of its novelty as well
as of its scope, is opposed to the qualitative view
of Aristotle;[2] the opinion that the essence of the
human spirit, as well as of the divine, nay, the essence
of all things, consists in activity; that, consequently,
the soul is always active, being conscious of its
own harmony at least in a confused way, even when not
conscious of external proportions; further, the doctrine
that nature loves simplicity, avoids the superfluous,
and is accustomed to accomplish large results with
a few principles—these remind one of Leibnitz.
At the same time, the law of parsimony and the methodological
conclusions concerning true hypotheses and real causes
(an hypothesis must not be an artificially constructed
set of fictions, forcibly adjusted to reality, but
is to trace back phenomena to their real grounds),
obedience to which enabled him to deduce
a priori
from causes the conclusions which Copernicus by fortunate
conjecture had gathered inductively from effects—these
made our thinker a forerunner of Newton. The
physical method of explanation must not be corrupted
either by theological conceptions (comets are entirely
natural phenomena!) or by anthropomorphic views, which
endow nature with spiritual powers.
[Footnote 1: See Sigwart, Kleine Schriften,
vol. i. p. 182 seq.; R. Eucken, Beitraege
zur Geschichte der neueren Philosophie, p. 54 seq.]
[Footnote 2: Aristotle erred when he considered
qualitative distinctions (idem and aliud)
ultimate. These are to be traced back to quantitative
differences, and the aliud or diversum
is to be replaced by plus et minus. There
is nothing absolutely light, but only relatively.
Since all things are distinguished only by “more
or less,” the possibility of mediating members
or proportions between them is given.]
Intermediate between Bacon and Descartes, both in
the order of time and in the order of fact, and a
co-founder of modern philosophy, stands Galileo Galilei
(1564-1641).[1] Galileo exhibits all the traits characteristic
of modern thinking: the reference from words to
things, from memory to perception and thought, from
authority to self-ascertained principles, from chance
opinion, arbitrary opinion, and the traditional doctrines
of the schools, to “knowledge,” that is,
to one’s own, well grounded, indisputable insight,
from the study of human affairs to the study of nature.
Study Aristotle, but do not become his slave; instead
of yielding yourselves captive to his views, use your