opposition of the qualities will not make itself evident.
But as soon as they come together, something takes
place—now the opposites (+_z_ and -
z)
seek to destroy or at least to disturb each other.
The reals defend themselves against the disturbance
which would follow if the opposites could destroy
each other, by each conserving its simple, unchangeable
quality,
i.e., by simply remaining self-identical.
Self-conservation against threatened
disturbances
from without (it may be compared to resistance against
pressure) is the only real change, and apparent change,
the empirical changes of things, to be explained from
this. That which changes is only the relations
between the beings, as a thing maintains itself now
against this and now against that other thing; the
relations, however, and their change are something
entirely contingent and indifferent to the existent.
In itself the self-conservation of a real is as uniform
as the quality which is conserved, but in virtue of
the changing relations (the variety of the disturbing
things) it can express itself for the observer in
manifold ways as force. The real itself changes
as little as a painting changes, for instance, when,
seen near at hand, the figures in it are clearly distinguished,
while for the distant observer, on the contrary, they
run together into an indistinguishable chaos.
Change has no meaning in the sphere of the existent.
Anyone who speaks thus has denied change, not deduced
it. Among the many objections experienced by
Herbart’s endeavor to explain the empirical
fact of change by his theory of self-conservation against
threatened disturbances Lotze’s is the most
cogent: The unsuccessful attempt to solve the
difficulties in the concept of becoming and action
is still instructive, for it shows that they cannot
be solved in this way—from the concept
of inflexible being. If the “together,”
the threatened disturbance, and the reaction against
the latter be taken as realities, then, in the affection
by the disturber, the concept of change remains uneliminated
and uncorrected; if they be taken as unreal concepts
auxiliary to thought, change is relegated from the
realm of being to the realm of seeming. Herbart
gives to them a kind of semi-reality, less true than
the unmoving ground of things (their unchangeable,
permanent qualities), and more true than their contradictory
exterior (the empirical appearance of change).
Between being and seeming he thrusts in, as though
between day and night, the twilight region of his
“contingent aspects,” with their relations,
which are nothing to the real, their disturbances,
which do not come to pass, and their self-conservations,
which are nothing but undisturbed continuance in existence
on the part of the real.