to it. On the one hand too much, and on the other
too little, is regarded as the original possession
of the understanding. The question “What
concepts are innate?” can be decided only by
answering the further question, What are the concepts
through which the faculty of judgment connects the
representations obtained from experience? These
connective concepts, these formal instruments of synthesis
are
a priori. The agreement of the two
schools is still greater in regard to the relation
of sense and understanding, notwithstanding the apparently
sharp contrast between them. The empiricist considers
thought transformed, sublimated perception, while
the rationalist sees in perception only confused and
less distinct thought. For the former concepts
are faded images of sensations, for the latter sensations
are concepts which have not yet become clear; the
difference is scarcely greater than if the one should
call ice frozen water, and the other should prefer
to call water melted ice. Both arrange intuition
and thought in a single series, and derive the one
from the other by enhancement or attenuation.
Both make the mistake of recognizing only a difference
in degree where a difference in kind exists.
In such a case only an energetic dualism can afford
help. Sense and understanding are not one and
the same cognitive power at different stages, but
two heterogeneous faculties. Sensation and thought
are not different in degree, but in kind. As
Descartes began with the metaphysical dualism of extension
and thought, so Kant begins with the noetical dualism
of intuition and thought.
Much more serious, however, than any of the mistakes
yet mentioned was a sin of omission of which the two
schools were alike guilty, and the recognition and
avoidance of which constituted in Kant’s own
eyes the distinctive character of his philosophy and
its principiant-advance beyond preceding systems.
The pre-Kantian thinker had proceeded to the discussion
of knowledge without raising the question of the
possibility of knowledge. He had approached
things in the full confidence that the human mind
was capable of cognizing them, and with a naive trust
in the power of reason to possess itself of the truth.
His trust was naive and ingenuous, because the idea
that it could deceive him had never entered his mind.
Now no matter whether this belief in man’s capacity
for knowledge and in the possibility of knowing things
is justifiable or not, and no matter how far it may
be justifiable, it was in any case untested; so that
when the skeptic approached with his objections the
dogmatist was defenseless. All previous philosophy,
so far as it had not been skeptical, had been, according
to Kant’s expression, dogmatic; that is, it had
held as an article of faith, and without precedent
inquiry, that we possess the power of cognizing objects.
It had not asked how this is possible; it had
not even asked what knowledge is, what may and must
be demanded of it, and by what means our reason is