the speculative gift, but only that it was surpassed
by his gift of reflection, and, to the latter, that
in regard to the positive element in religion he judged
very differently from the deists and appreciated the
historical element more justly than they—if
not to the same extent as Lessing and Herder.
We do not need to lay great stress on the fact that
Kant had a lively consciousness that he was making
a contribution to thought, and that the Illumination
contemplated this new doctrine without comprehending
it, in order to recognize that the difference between
his efforts and achievements and those of the Illumination
is far greater than their kinship. For although
Kant is upon common ground with it, in so far as he
adheres to its motto, “Have courage to use thine
own understanding, become a man, cease to trust thyself
to the guidance of others, and free thyself in all
fields from the yoke of authority,” and, although
besides such formal injunctions to freedom of thought,
he also shares in certain material tendencies and
convictions (the turning from the world to man, the
attempt at a synthesis of reason and experience, and
the belief in a religion of reason); yet in method
and results, he stands like a giant among a race of
dwarfs, like one instructed, who judges from principles,
among men of opinion, who merely stick results together,
a methodical systematizer among well-meaning but impotent
eclectics. The philosophy of the Illumination
is related to that of Kant as argument to science,
as halting mediation to principiant resolution, as
patchwork to creation out of full resources, yet at
the same time as wish to deed and as negative preparation
to positive achievement. It was undeniably of
great value to the Kantian criticism that the Illumination
had created a point of intersection for the various
tendencies of thought, and had brought about the approximation
and mutual contact of the opposing systems which then
existed, while, at the same time, it had crumbled
them to pieces, and thus awakened the need for a new,
more firmly and more deeply founded system.
%4. The Faith Philosophy.%
The philosophers of feeling or faith stand in the
same relation to the German Illumination as Rousseau
to the French. Here also the rights of feeling
are vindicated against those of the knowing reason.
Among the distinguished representatives of this anti-rationalistic
tendency Hamann led the way, Herder was the most prolific,
and Jacobi the clearest. That the fountain of
certitude is to be sought not in discriminating thought,
but in intuition, experience, revelation, and tradition;
that the highest truths can be felt only and not proved;
that all existing things are incomprehensible, because
individual—these are convictions which,
before Jacobi defended them as based on scientific
principles, had been vehemently proclaimed by that
singular man, J.G. Hamann (died 1788) of Koenigsberg.
From an unprinted review by Hamann, Herder drew the
objections which his “Metacritique” raises
against Kant’s Critique of Reason—that
the division of matter and form, of sensibility and
understanding, is inadmissible; that Kant misunderstood
the significance of language, which is just where
sensibility and understanding unite, etc.