to-day, though this mutilation and leveling down of
the most daring of Leibnitz’s hypotheses was
perhaps entirely advantageous for Wolff’s impression
on his contemporaries; what appeared questionable to
him would no doubt have repelled them also. Leibnitz’s
two leading ideas, the theory of monads and the pre-established
harmony, were most of all affected by this process
of toning down. Wolff weakens the former by attributing
a representative power only to actual souls, which
are capable of consciousness, although he holds that
bodies are compounded of simple beings and that the
latter are endowed with (a not further defined) force.
He limits the application of the pre-established harmony
to the relation of body and soul, which to Leibnitz
was only a case especially favorable for the illustration
of the hypothesis. By such trifling the real meaning
of both these ideas is sacrificed and their bloom
rubbed off.—While depth is lacking in Wolff’s
thinking, he is remarkable for his power of systematization,
his persevering diligence, and his logical earnestness,
so that the praise bestowed on him by Kant, that he
was the author of the spirit of thoroughness in Germany,
was well deserved. He, too, finds the end of
philosophy in the enlightenment of the understanding,
the improvement of the heart, and, ultimately, in
the promotion of the happiness of mankind. But
while Thomasius demanded as a condition of such universal
intelligibility and usefulness that, discarding the
scholastic garb, philosophy should appear in the form
of easy ratiocination, Wolff, on the other hand, regards
methodical procedure and certainty in results as indispensable
to its usefulness, and, in order to this certainty,
insists on distinctness of conception and cogency of
proof. He demands a
philosophia et certa et
utilis. If, finally, his methodical deliberateness,
especially in his later works, leads him into wearisome
diffuseness, this pedantry is made good by his genuinely
German, honest spirit, which manifests itself agreeably
in his judgment on practical questions.
[Footnote 1: Reasonable Thoughts on the Powers
of the Human Understanding, 1712; Reasonable
Thoughts on God, the World, and the Soul of Man, also
on All Things in General, 1719 (Notes to
this 1724); Reasonable Thoughts on the Conduct
of Man, 1720; Reasonable Thoughts on the Social
Life of Man, 1721; Reasonable Thoughts on the
Operations of Nature, 1723; Reasonable Thoughts
on the Purposes of Natural Things, 1724; Reasonable
Thoughts on the Parts of Man, Animals, and Plants,
1725, all in German. Besides these there are
extensive Latin treatises (1728-53) on Logic, Ontology,
Cosmology, Empirical and Rational Psychology, Natural
Theology, and all branches of Practical Philosophy.
Detailed extracts may be found in Erdmann’s
Versuch einer wissenschaftlichen Darstellung,
ii. 2. The best account of the Wolffian philosophy
has been given by Zeller (pp. 211-273).]