in the first half. His lively and many-sided
receptivity, active industry, clever and combative
eloquence, and enthusiastic disposition qualified him
for this role beyond all his contemporaries, who testify
that they owe even more to his stimulating conversation
than to his writings. He commenced by bringing
Shaftesbury’s
Inquiry into Virtue and Merit
to the notice of his countrymen; and then turned his
sword, on the one hand, against the atheists, to refute
whom, he thought, a single glance into the microscope
was sufficient, and, on the other, against the traditional
belief in a God of anger and revenge, who takes pleasure
in bathing in the tears of mankind. Then followed
a period of skepticism, which is well illustrated by
the prayer in the
Thoughts on the Interpretation
of Nature, 1754: O God! I do not know
whether thou art, but I will guide my thoughts and
actions as though thou didst see me think and act,
etc. Under the influence of Holbach’s
circle he finally reached (in the
Conversation between
D’Alembert and Diderot, and
D’Alembert’s
Dream, written in 1769, but not published until
1830, in vol. iv. of the
Memoires, Correspondance,
et Ouvrages Inedits de Diderot) the position of
naturalistic monism—there exists but one
great individual, the All. Though he had formerly
distinguished thinking substance from material substance,
and had based the immortality of the soul on the unity
of sensation and the unity of the ego, he now makes
sensation a universal and essential property of matter
(
la pierre sent), declares the talk about the
simplicity of the soul metaphysico-theological nonsense,
calls the brain a self-playing instrument, ridicules
self-esteem, shame, and repentance as the absurd folly
of a being that imputes to itself merit or demerit
for necessary actions, and recognizes no other immortality
than that of posthumous fame. But even amid these
extreme conclusions, his enthusiasm for virtue remains
too intense to allow him to assent to the audacious
theories of La Mettrie and Helvetius.
[Footnote 1: Works in twenty-two vols.,
Paris, Briere, 1821; latest edition, 1875 seq.
Cf. on Diderot the fine work by Karl Rosenkranz, Diderots
Leben und Werke, 1866.]
French natural science also tended toward materialism.
Buffon (Natural History, 1749 seq) endeavors
to facilitate the mechanical explanation of the phenomena
of life by the assumption of living molecules, from
which visible organisms are built up. Robinet
(On Nature, 1761 seq.), availing himself
of Spinozistic and Leibnitzian conceptions, goes still
further, in that he endows every particle of matter
with sensation, looks on the whole world as a succession
of living beings with increasing mentality, and subjects
the interaction of the material and psychical sides
of the individual, as well as the relation of pleasure
and pain in the universe, to a law of harmonious compensation.