which it reconstructs from its central point, and to
prepare him for the study (which, of course, even
the best exposition cannot replace) of the works of
the thinkers themselves. Its excessive simplification
of problems is not of great moment in the first introduction
to a system [English translation of vol. iii. book
2 (1st ed.),
A Commentary on Kant’s Critick
of the Pure Reason, by J.P. Mahaffy, London,
1866; vol. i. part 1 and part 2, book 1,
Descartes
and his School, by J, P. Gordy, New York, 1887;
of vol. v. chaps, i.-v.,
A Critique of Kant,
by W.S. Hough, London, 1888.—TR.].
Wilhelm Windelband
(Geschichte der neueren Philosophie,
2 vols., 1878 and 1880, to Hegel and Herbart inclusive)
accentuates the connection of philosophy with general
culture and the particular sciences, and emphasizes
philosophical method. This work is pleasant reading,
yet, in the interest of clearness, we could wish that
the author had given more of positive information
concerning the content of the doctrines treated, instead
of merely advancing reflections on them. A projected
third volume is to trace the development of philosophy
down to the present time. Windelband’s
compendium,
Geschichte der Philosophie, 1890-91,
is distinguished from other expositions by the fact
that, for the most part, it confines itself to a history
of
problems. Baumann’s
Geschichte
der Philosophie, 1890, aims to give a detailed
account of those thinkers only who have advanced views
individual either in their content or in their proof.
Eduard Zeller has given his
Geschichte der deutschen
Philosophie seit Leibniz (1873; 2d ed., 1875)
the benefit of the same thorough and comprehensive
knowledge and mature judgment which have made his
Philosophie der Griechen a classic. [Bowen’s
Modern Philosophy, New York, 1857 (6th ed.,
1891); Royce’s
Spirit of Modern Philosophy,
1892.—TR.]
Eugen Duehring’s hypercritical Kritische
Geschichte der Philosophie (1869; 3d ed., 1878)
can hardly be recommended to students. Lewes (German
translation, 1876) assumes a positivistic standpoint;
Thilo (1874), a position exclusively Herbartian; A.
Stoeckl (3d ed., 1889) writes from the standpoint
of confessional Catholicism; Vincenz Knauer (2d ed.,
1882) is a Guentherian. With the philosophico-historical
work of Chr. W. Sigwart (1854), and one of the
same date by Oischinger, we are not intimately acquainted.
Expositions of philosophy since Kant have been given
by the Hegelian, C.L. Michelet (a larger one
in 2 vols., 1837-38, and a smaller one, 1843); by
Chalybaeus (1837; 5th ed., 1860, formerly very popular
and worthy of it, English, 1854); by Fr. K. Biedermann
(1842-43); by Carl Fortlage (1852, Kantio-Fichtean
standpoint); and by Friedrich Harms (1876). The
last of these writers unfortunately did not succeed
in giving a sufficiently clear and precise, not to
say tasteful, form to the valuable ideas and original
conceptions in which his work is rich. The very
popular exposition by an anonymous author of Hegelian
tendencies, Deutschlands Denker seit Kant (Dessau,
1851), hardly deserves mention.