and not carried out with sufficient consistency.
The dispute between the two remaining contestants
may be easily and equitably settled by making the
simple distinction between forerunner and beginner,
between path-breaker and founder. The entrance
of a new historical era is not accompanied by an audible
click, like the beginning of a new piece on a music-box,
but is gradually effected. A considerable period
may intervene between the point when the new movement
flashes up, not understood and half unconscious of
itself, and the time when it appears on the stage in
full strength and maturity, recognizing itself as
new and so acknowledged by others: the period
of ferment between the Middle Ages and modern times
lasted almost two centuries. It is in the end
little more than logomachy to discuss whether this
time of anticipation and desire, of endeavor and partial
success, in which the new struggles with the old without
conquering it, and the opposite tendencies in the
conflicting views of the world interplay in a way
at once obscure and wayward, is to be classed as the
epilogue of the old era or the prologue of the new.
The simple solution to take it as a
transition
period, no longer mediaeval but not yet modern,
has met with fairly general acceptance. Nicolas
of Cusa (1401-64) was the first to announce
fundamental
principles of modern philosophy—he is
the leader in this intermediate preparatory period.
Descartes (1596-1650) brought forward the first
system—he
is the father of modern philosophy.
A brief survey of the literature may be added in conclusion:
Heinrich Ritter’s Geschichte der neueren
Philosophie (vols. ix.-xii. of his Geschichte
der Philosophie), 1850-53, to Wolff and Rousseau,
has been superseded by more recent works, J.E.
Erdmann’s able Versuch einer wissenschaftlichen
Darstellung der neueren Philosophie (6 vols., 1834-53)
gives in appendices literal excerpts from non-German
writers; the same author’s Grundriss der
Geschichte der Philosophie (2 vols., 1869; 3d ed.,
1878) contains at the end the first exposition of German
Philosophy since the Death of Hegel [English translation
in 3 vols., edited by W. S. Hough, 1890.—TR.].
Ueberweg’s Grundriss (7th ed. by M. Heinze,
1888) is indispensable for reference on account of
the completeness of its bibliographical notes, which,
however, are confusing to the beginner [English translation
by G.S. Morris, with additions by the translator,
Noah Porter, and Vincenzo Botta, New York, 1872-74.—TR.].
The most detailed and brilliant exposition has been
given by Kuno Fischer (1854 seq.; 3d ed., 1878 seq.;
the same author’s Baco und seine Nachfolger,
2d ed., 1875,—English translation, 1857,
by Oxenford,—supplements the first two
volumes of the Geschichte der neueren Philosophie).
This work, which is important also as a literary achievement,
is better fitted than any other to make the reader
at home in the ideal world of the great philosophers,