him contented with himself and acceptable to God and
man, but great states require stronger motives to labor
and industry in order to be prosperous. A people
among whom frugality, self-denial, and quietness of
spirit were the rule would remain poor and ignorant.
Besides holding that virtue furthers the happiness
of society, Shaftesbury makes a second mistake in
assuming that human nature includes unselfish inclinations.
It is not innate love and goodness that make us social,
but our passions and weaknesses (above all, fear);
man is by nature self-seeking. All actions, including
the so-called virtues, spring from vanity and egoism;
thus it has always been, thus it is in every grade
of society. In social life, indeed, we dare not
display all these desires openly, nor satisfy them
at will. Shrewd lawgivers have taught men to
conceal their natural passions and to limit them by
artificial ones, persuading them that renunciation
is true happiness, on the ground that through it we
attain the supreme good—reputation among,
and the esteem of our fellows. Since then honor
and shame have become the strongest motives and have
incited men to that which is called virtue,
i.e.,
to actions which apparently imply the sacrifice of
selfish inclinations for the good of society, while
they are really done out of pride and self-love.
By constantly feigning noble sentiments before others
man comes, finally, to deceive himself, believing
himself a being whose happiness consists in the renunciation
of self and all that is earthly, and in the thought
of his moral excellence.—The crass assumptions
in Mandeville’s reasoning are evident at a glance.
After analyzing virtue into the suppression of desire,
after labeling the impulse after moral approbation
vanity, lawful self-love egoism, and rational acquisitiveness
avarice, it was easy for him to prove that it is vice
which makes the individual industrious and the state
prosperous, that virtue is seldom found, and that if
it were universal it would become injurious to society.
With different shading and with less one-sidedness,
Bolingbroke (cf. p. 193) defended the standpoint of
naturalism. God has created us for happiness
in common; we are destined to assist one another.
Happiness is attainable in society alone, and society
cannot exist without justice and benevolence.
He who exercises virtue, i.e., promotes the
good of the species, promotes at the same time his
own good. All actions spring from self-love,
which, guided at first by an immediate instinct, and
later, by reason developed through experience, extends
itself over ever widening spheres. We love ourselves
in our relatives, in our friends, further still, in
our country, finally, in humanity, so that self-love
and social love coincide, and we are impelled to virtue
by the combined motives of interest and duty.
This is an ethic of common sense from the standpoint
of the cultured man of the world—which
at the proper time has the right, no doubt, to gain
itself a hearing.