is an activity of the body, and not its essential
characteristic. The mind does not receive ideas
until external objects occasion perception in it through
impressions, which it is not able to avert. The
understanding may be compared to a mirror, which, without
independent activity and without being consulted, takes
up the images of things. Some of the simple ideas
which have been mentioned above represent the properties
of things as they really are, others not. The
former class includes all ideas of reflection (for
we are ourselves the immediate object of the inner
sense); but among the ideas of sensation those only
which come from different senses, hence extension,
motion and rest, number, figure, and, further, solidity,
are to be accounted primary qualities, i.
e., such as are actual copies of the properties
of bodies. All other ideas, on the contrary,
have no resemblance to properties of bodies; they represent
merely the ways in which things act, and are not copies
of things. The ideas of secondary or derivative
qualities (hard and soft, warm and cold, colors and
sounds, tastes and odors) are in the last analysis
caused—as are the primary—by
motion, but not perceived as such. Yellow and
warm are merely sensations in us, which we erroneously
ascribe to objects; with equal right we might ascribe
to fire, as qualities inherent in it, the changes
in form and color which it produces in wax and the
pain which it causes in the finger brought into proximity
with it. The warmth and the brightness of the
blaze, the redness, the pleasant taste, and the aromatic
odor of the strawberry, exist in these bodies merely
as the power to produce such sensations in us by stimulation
of the skin, the eye, the palate, and the nose.
If we remove the perceptions of them, they disappear
as such, and their causes alone remain—the
bulk, figure, number, texture, and motion of the insensible
particles. The ground of the illusion lies in
the fact that such qualities as color, etc., bear
no resemblance to their causes, in no wise point to
these, and in themselves contain naught of bulk, density,
figure, and motion, and that our senses are too weak
to discover the material particles and their primary
qualities.—The distinction between qualities
of the first and second order—first advanced
by the ancient atomists, revived by Galileo and Descartes
on the threshold of the modern period, retained by
Locke, and still customary in the natural science
of the day—forms an important link in the
transition from the popular view of all sense-qualities
as properties of things in themselves to Kant’s
position, that spatial and temporal qualities also
belong to phenomena alone, and are based merely on
man’s subjective mode of apprehension, while
the real properties of things in themselves are unknowable.