and scientific discoveries and religious reforms which
marked the entrance of the modern period. It is
true, indeed, that the transition brought about by
Kant’s noetical and ethical revolution was of
great significance,—more significant even
than the Socratic period, with which we are fond of
comparing it; much that was new was woven on, much
of the old, weakened, broken, destroyed. And yet,
if we take into account the historical after-influence
of Cartesianism, we shall find that the thread was
only knotted and twisted by Kantianism, not cut through.
The continued power of the pre-Kantian modes of thought
is shown by the fact that Spinoza has been revived
in Fichte and Schelling, Leibnitz in Herbart and Hegel,
the sensationalism of the French Illuminati in Feuerbach;
and that even materialism, which had been struck down
by the criticism of the reason (one would have thought
forever), has again raised its head. Even that
most narrow tendency of the early philosophy of the
modern period, the apotheosis of cognition is,—in
spite of the moralistic counter-movement of Kant and
Fichte,—the controlling motive in the last
of the great idealistic systems, while it also continues
to exercise a marvelously powerful influence on the
convictions of our Hegel-weary age, alike within the
sphere of philosophy and (still more) without it.
In view of the intimate relations between contemporary
inquiry and the progress of thought since the beginning
of the modern period, acquaintance with the latter,
which it is the aim of this
History to facilitate,
becomes a pressing duty. To study the history
of philosophy since Descartes is to study the pre-conditions
of contemporary philosophy.
We begin with an outline sketch of the general characteristics
of modern philosophy. These may be most conveniently
described by comparing them with the characteristics
of ancient and of mediaeval philosophy. The character
of ancient philosophy or Greek philosophy,—for
they are practically the same,—is predominantly
aesthetic. The Greek holds beauty and truth closely
akin and inseparable; “cosmos” is his common
expression for the world and for ornament. The
universe is for him a harmony, an organism, a work
of art, before which he stands in admiration and reverential
awe. In quiet contemplation, as with the eye
of a connoisseur, he looks upon the world or the individual
object as a well-ordered whole, more disposed to enjoy
the congruity of its parts than to study out its ultimate
elements. He prefers contemplation to analysis,
his thought is plastic, not anatomical. He finds
the nature of the object in its form; and ends give
him the key to the comprehension of events. Discovering
human elements everywhere, he is always ready with
judgments of worth—the stars move in circles
because circular motion is the most perfect; the right
is better than left, upper finer than lower, that
which precedes more beautiful than that which follows.
Thinkers in whom this aesthetic reverence is weaker