hand, that it does too much or too little, or the
right thing in the wrong way, so that the spirit of
philosophy seems to have erred in the choice and the
preparation of its instrument. But the reverse
side of the picture must also be taken into account.
The thinking spirit is more limited, it is true, than
were desirable for the perfect execution of a definite
logical task; but, on the other hand, it is far too
rich as well. A soulless play of concepts would
certainly not help the cause, and there is no disadvantage
in the failure of the history of philosophy to proceed
so directly and so scholastically, as, for instance,
in the system of Hegel. A graded series of interconnected
general forces mediate between the logical Idea and
the individual thinker—the spirit of the
people, of the age, of the thinker’s vocation,
of his time of life, which are felt by the individual
as part of himself and whose impulses he unconsciously
obeys. In this way the modifying, furthering,
hindering correlation of higher and lower, of the
ruler with his commands and the servant with his more
or less willing obedience, is twice repeated, the
situation being complicated further by the fact that
the subject affected by these historical forces himself
helps to make history. The most important factor
in philosophical progress is, of course, the state
of inquiry at the time, the achievements of the thinkers
of the immediately preceding age; and in this relation
of a philosopher to his predecessors, again, a distinction
must be made between a logical and a psychological
element. The successor often commences his support,
his development, or his refutation at a point quite
unwelcome to the constructive historian. At all
events, if we may judge from the experience of the
past, too much caution cannot be exercised in setting
up formal laws for the development of thought.
According to the law of contradiction and reconciliation,
a Schopenhauer must have followed directly after Leibnitz,
to oppose his pessimistic ethelism to the optimistic
intellectualism of the latter; when, in turn, a Schleiermacher,
to give an harmonic resolution of the antithesis into
a concrete doctrine of feeling, would have made a fine
third. But it turned out otherwise, and we must
be content.
* * * *
*
The estimate of the value of the history of philosophy
in general, given at the start, is the more true of
the history of modern philosophy, since the movement
introduced by the latter still goes on unfinished.
We are still at work on the problems which were brought
forward by Descartes, Locke, and Leibnitz, and which
Kant gathered up into the critical or transcendental
question. The present continues to be governed
by the ideal of culture which Bacon proposed and Fichte
exalted to a higher level; we all live under the unweakened
spell of that view of the world which was developed
in hostile opposition to Scholasticism, and through
the enduring influence of those mighty geographical