afternoon with sundry abstruse speculations, and putting
them off to the following week for a satisfaction
of their doubts; but why should he treat posterity
in the same scurvy manner, or leave the world without
quitting scores with it? I question whether Mr.
Tooke was himself in possession of his pretended
nostrum,
and whether, after trying hard at a definition of the
verb as a distinct part of speech, as a terrier-dog
mumbles a hedge-hog, he did not find it too much for
him, and leave it to its fate. It is also a pity
that Mr. Tooke spun out his great work with prolix
and dogmatical dissertations on irrelevant matters;
and after denying the old metaphysical theories of
language, should attempt to found a metaphysical theory
of his own on the nature and mechanism of language.
The nature of words, he contended (it was the basis
of his whole system) had no connection with the nature
of things or the objects of thought; yet he afterwards
strove to limit the nature of things and of the human
mind by the technical structure of language. Thus
he endeavours to shew that there are no abstract ideas,
by enumerating two thousand instances of words, expressing
abstract ideas, that are the past participles of certain
verbs. It is difficult to know what he means by
this. On the other hand, he maintains that “a
complex idea is as great an absurdity as a complex
star,” and that words only are complex.
He also makes out a triumphant list of metaphysical
and moral non-entities, proved to be so on the pure
principle that the names of these non-entities are
participles, not nouns, or names of things. That
is strange in so close a reasoner and in one who maintained
that all language was a masquerade of words, and that
the class to which they grammatically belonged had
nothing to do with the class of ideas they represented.
It is now above twenty years since the two quarto
volumes of the Diversions of Purley were published,
and fifty since the same theory was promulgated in
the celebrated Letter to Dunning. Yet it
is a curious example of the Spirit of the Age
that Mr. Lindley Murray’s Grammar (a work out
of which Mr. C—— helps himself to
English, and Mr. M—— to style[B])
has proceeded to the thirtieth edition in complete
defiance of all the facts and arguments there laid
down. He defines a noun to be the name of a thing.
Is quackery a thing, i.e. a substance?
He defines a verb to be a word signifying to be,
to do, or to suffer. Are being, action, suffering
verbs? He defines an adjective to be the name
of a quality. Are not wooden, golden, substantial
adjectives? He maintains that there are six cases
in English nouns [C], that is, six various terminations
without any change of termination at all, and that
English verbs have all the moods, tenses, and persons
that the Latin ones have. This is an extraordinary
stretch of blindness and obstinacy. He very formally
translates the Latin Grammar into English (as so many