one hand it aimed at the public good, while on the
other hand it ministered to the personal objects and
in fact the personal vengeance of the ruler.
Gracchus earnestly laboured to find a remedy for
social evils, and to check the spread of pauperism;
yet he at the same time intentionally reared up a
street proletariate of the worst kind in the capital
by his distributions of corn, which were designed
to be, and became, a premium to all the lazy and hungry
civic rabble. Gracchus censured in the bitterest
terms the venality of the senate, and in particular
laid bare with unsparing and just severity the scandalous
traffic which Manius Aquillius had driven with the
provinces of Asia Minor;(25) yet it was through the
efforts of the same man that the sovereign populace
of the capital got itself alimented, in return for
its cares of government, by the body of its subjects.
Gracchus warmly disapproved the disgraceful spoliation
of the provinces, and not only instituted proceedings
of wholesome severity in particular cases, but also
procured the abolition of the thoroughly insufficient
senatorial courts, before which even Scipio Aemilianus
had vainly staked his whole influence to bring the
most decided criminals to punishment. Yet he
at the same time, by the introduction of courts composed
of merchants, surrendered the provincials with their
hands fettered to the party of material interests,
and thereby to a despotism still more unscrupulous
than that of the aristocracy had been; and he introduced
into Asia a taxation, compared with which even the
form of taxation current after the Carthaginian model
in Sicily might be called mild and humane—
just because on the one hand he needed the party of
moneyed men, and on the other hand required new and
comprehensive resources to meet his distributions
of grain and the other burdens newly imposed on the
finances. Gracchus beyond doubt desired a firm
administration and a well-regulated dispensing of
justice, as numerous thoroughly judicious ordinances
testify; yet his new system of administration rested
on a continuous series of individual usurpations only
formally legalized, and he intentionally drew the
judicial system—which every well-ordered
state will endeavour as far as possible to place, if
not above political parties, at any rate aloof from
them—into the midst of the whirlpool of
revolution. Certainly the blame of these conflicting
tendencies in Gaius Gracchus is chargeable to a very
great extent on his position rather than on himself
personally. On the very threshold of the -tyrannis-
he was confronted by the fatal dilemma, moral and
political, that the same man had at one and the same
time to maintain his ground, we may say, as a robber-chieftain
and to lead the state as its first citizen—a
dilemma to which Pericles, Caesar, and Napoleon had
also to make dangerous sacrifices. But the conduct
of Gaius Gracchus cannot be wholly explained from
this necessity; along with it there worked in him the