but every manifestation of the primitive God was in
its turn divine, the stars above all, but also the
earth, the vine, the soul of the illustrious mortal
whom the people honoured as a hero, and in fact every
departed spirit of a former man. This philosophy
was really better adapted for Rome than for the land
where it first arose. The objection of the pious
believer, that the god of the Stoic had neither sex
nor age nor corporeality and was converted from a
person into a conception, had a meaning in Greece,
but not in Rome. The coarse allegorizing and
moral purification, which were characteristic of the
Stoical doctrine of the gods, destroyed the very marrow
of the Hellenic mythology; but the plastic power of
the Romans, scanty even in their epoch of simplicity,
had produced no more than a light veil enveloping
the original intuition or the original conception,
out of which the divinity had arisen—a veil
that might be stripped off without special damage.
Pallas Athene might be indignant, when she found
herself suddenly transmuted into the conception of
memory: Minerva had hitherto been in reality not
much more. The supernatural Stoic, and the allegoric
Roman, theology coincided on the whole in their result.
But, even if the philosopher was obliged to designate
individual propositions of the priestly lore as doubtful
or as erroneous—as when the Stoics, for
example, rejecting the doctrine of apotheosis, saw
in Hercules, Castor, and Pollux nothing but the spirits
of distinguished men, or as when they could not allow
the images of the gods to be regarded as representations
of divinity—it was at least not the habit
of the adherents of Zeno to make war on these erroneous
doctrines and to overthrow the false gods; on the
contrary, they everywhere evinced respect and reverence
for the religion of the land even in its weaknesses.
The inclination also of the Stoa towards a casuistic
morality and towards a systematic treatment of the
professional sciences was quite to the mind of the
Romans, especially of the Romans of this period, who
no longer like their fathers practised in unsophisticated
fashion self-government and good morals, but resolved
the simple morality of their ancestors into a catechism
of allowable and non-allowable actions; whose grammar
and jurisprudence, moreover, urgently demanded a methodical
treatment, without possessing the ability to develop
such a treatment of themselves.
Wide Influence of Stoicism
Panaetius
So this philosophy thoroughly incorporated itself, as a plant borrowed no doubt from abroad but acclimatized on Italian soil, with the Roman national economy, and we meet its traces in the most diversified spheres of action. Its earliest appearance beyond doubt goes further back; but the Stoa was first raised to full influence in the higher ranks of Roman society by means of the group which gathered round Scipio Aemilianus. Panaetius of Rhodes, the instructor of Scipio and of all Scipio’s intimate friends